Alfred Schutz

First published Tue Oct 29, 2002; substantive revision Tue Dec 21, 2021

Alfred Schutz (b. 1899, d. 1959), more than any other phenomenologist, attempted to relate the thought of Edmund Husserl to the social world and the social sciences. His Phenomenology of the Social World supplied philosophical foundations for Max Weber’s sociology and for economics, with which he was familiar through contacts with colleagues of the Austrian school. When Schutz fled Hitler’s Anschluss of Austria and immigrated to the United States in 1939, he developed his thought further in relationship to the social sciences, American pragmatism, logical empiricism, and to various other fields of endeavor such as music and literature. His work has been influential on new movements in sociological thought such as ethnomethodology and conversation analysis.

1. Life and Influence

Vienna-born Alfred Schutz joined the artillery division of the Austrian army during World War I and served on the Italian front before returning to pursue studies at the University of Vienna. There Schutz studied law, social science, and business with renowned figures such as Hans Kelsen and Ludwig von Mises, but his most significant educational experience occurred while he was a member of the Mises Circle, one of many Viennese circles, of which the “Schlick Circle” was the most famous. In the interdisciplinary Mises Circle, Schutz formed friendships that would continue throughout the cataclysmic decades of the 1930s and 1940s and that included, among others, economists Gottfried von Haberler, Friedrich A. von Hayek, Fritz Machlup, Oskar Morgenstern, philosopher Felix Kaufmann, and political scientist Eric Voegelin. While continuing to pursue his academic interests, in 1927 Schutz was named executive officer of Reitler and Company, a leading Viennese banking firm with international business relations, and thus he commenced a life-long pattern that led Edmund Husserl to describe him as “a banker by day and a philosopher by night.”

From the beginning, Schutz had been taken with the methodological writings of Max Weber, who had lectured in Vienna in the summer of 1918 and whose work was immensely popular among Viennese intellectuals. However, Schutz felt that Weber’s work rested on tacit, unexamined presuppositions resulting from his lack of interest in fundamental epistemological problems that had no direct bearing on his special sociological problems. In 1925–1927, Schutz turned to Henri Bergson’s philosophy of consciousness and inner time in order to clarify notions such as meaning, action, and intersubjectivity, and his results have been collected in manuscripts published as Life Forms and Meaning Structure. Dissatisfied, though, with his analyses of temporality to the extent that he never published them and prompted by comments of Felix Kaufmann, he discovered the relevance of the phenomenology of the consciousness of inner time of Edmund Husserl (1859–1938). He then went on to produce his major life’s work, The Phenomenology of the Social World (1932), a work for which Husserl praised him as “an earnest and profound phenomenologist.” He spent the rest of the 1930s authoring brief essays showing how his phenomenology of the social world could come to terms with the economic thought of Mises and Hayek. Also, before any direct encounter with American pragmatism, he developed a manuscript on personality in the social world that stressed the pragmatic elements of the everyday social world.

Schutz’s career, academic and business, was thoroughly convulsed when Adolf Hitler implemented the annexation (Anschluss) of Austria by Germany on March 13, 1938, especially since he, on a business trip in Paris, was separated for three months from his own family, whose emigration to Paris he finally arranged. As an international lawyer and businessperson, he was able to assist numerous intellectuals to escape Austria, but the westward movement of the Nazi juggernaut eventually compelled him to immigrate with his family to the United States on July 14, 1939.

In the United States, he continued assisting immigrants and working with Reitler and Company in reestablishing its business, and he supported the United States war effort by reporting on German and Austrian economic matters for the Board of Economic Warfare. He also cooperated with Marvin Farber in founding the International Phenomenological Society, whose initial turf-battles he often mediated, and in instituting and editing Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. In 1943, Schutz began teaching sociology and philosophy courses on The Graduate Faculty of The New School for Social Research, and his responsibilities included presenting papers in the school-wide General Seminar, supervising dissertations, and serving as chair of the Philosophy Department from 1952–1956. In spite of his many activities, he managed to carry on an extensive philosophical correspondence with Farber, Aron Gurwitsch, Fritz Machlup, Eric Voegelin, and Maurice Natanson, his graduate student from 1951 to 1953. However, to date, only the correspondences with Gurwitsch and Voegelin have been published. While in the United States, Schutz published a collection of articles on a wide variety of topics, explaining and criticizing Husserl’s thought; examining the works of American philosophers such as William James or George Santanyana; engaging continental philosophers such as Max Scheler or Jean-Paul Sartre; developing his own philosophical positions on the social sciences, temporality, language, multiple realities, responsibility, and symbolism; addressing socio-political questions dealing with strangers, homecomers, well-informed citizens, and equality; and treating themes in literature and music.

Several thinkers have continued Schutz’s tradition in philosophy and sociology, such as Maurice Natanson who emphasized the tension between individual, existential and social, anonymizing dimensions of everyday life experience. Thomas Luckmann, who served as co-author for the posthumous publication of Schutz’s The Structures of the Life-World, developed the sociology of knowledge implications of Schutz’s thought and stressed the differences between science and the life-world as well as the importance of language, symbolism, and the moral order of society. While John O’Neill has fused Schutz’s thought with that of Merleau-Ponty by focusing on the lived, communicative body, Richard Grathoff has investigated the experience of normality within the bounded and situated context of a milieu. Ilja Srubar developed the pragmatic dimensions of Schutz’s thought and several of its economic and political implications, Lester Embree clarified his typology of the sciences, and Fred Kersten has expanded his aesthetic insights. Drawing on Schutz’s thought, Harold Garfinkel launched ethnomethodology, and George Psathas, a commentator on ethnomethodology, played a key role initiating the new discipline of conversation analysis. Several other scholars worldwide have dedicated themselves to Schutz’s work and to the development of his insights, and Germany, Japan, and the United States are home to archives containing Schutz’s work and correspondence.

2. The Phenomenology of the Social World

In his principal work, Schutz placed three chapters of philosophical discussion between introductory and concluding chapters that discussed the social scientific positions his philosophy attempted to engage. In the initial chapter Schutz praised Max Weber’s views on value-freedom in social science and the autonomy of science vis-à-vis other activities (e.g. politics), and he commended Weber’s methodological individualism and ideal-type methodology. In addition, he applauded Weber’s refusal to reduce the social sciences to the natural sciences, while allowing their ideal-typical results to be testable for adequacy. However, Schutz also supplemented Weber, pointing out how interpretation was involved even in selecting an experience out of one’s stream of experience and highlighting how the meaning of an action to an actor depended upon the project guiding the extended temporal process of the sub-acts leading to its realization.

These initial criticisms of Weber required Schutz to develop his own theory of meaning and action, beginning with Husserl’s study of the consciousness of internal time, in particular consciousness’s capacity to capture reflectively and distinguish lived experiences, which at first appear as undefined phases melting into each other. Schutz had appropriated this notion of flowing consciousness, or duration, from Bergson, on whom he had relied in the manuscripts later published as Life Forms and Meaning Structure. Those manuscripts, for analytic purposes, split the ego, indivisible in its lived experience, into ideal-typical constructs of various life forms, that included the “I” living in duration, remembering, acting, thinking, and relating to a “Thou.” Though Schutz never made explicit his reasons for not publishing those earlier manuscripts, Helmut Wagner rightly speculated that he was ill at ease since one could only have access to duration through acts of memory, which, of course, constituted a life-form entirely separate from duration itself. As a result of this methodology relying on distinct ideal-types, duration began to appear as an inaccessible Ding-an-sich. Husserl’s account of the consciousness of inner time remedied just this problem by carefully describing how the stream of duration was changed at every moment into a remembered having-just-been-thus, as the primal impression passed into into primary remembrance, or retention. The continuum extending backward from the now of the primal impression through its retentions formed a “specious” present, to which the reflective acts of secondary remembrance, that is, recollection or reproduction, turned, differentiating one experience from another. In sum, Husserl’s phenomenological description of experience uncovered the process of retention that bridged the duration/(reflective) memory gap that had bedeviled Schutz’s earlier efforts insofar as he had relied on an ideal-typical methodology, which prevented insight into what goes on within conscious processes themselves.

Schutz, though, turned the Husserlian account of temporality in the direction of an action theory, demarcating levels of passive experience (e.g. bodily reflexes), spontaneous activity without a guiding project (e.g., acts of noticing environmental stimuli), and deliberately planned and projected activity, known technically as “action” (e.g., writing a book). In planning an action to be realized in the future, one relies on reflective acts of “projection,” like those found in reflective memory, only now oriented in a future as opposed to past direction. Through such reflectivity, one imagines a project as completed in future perfect tense, that is, what will have been realized after one’s acting, and this project, also of central importance for Martin Heidegger and the pragmatist tradition, establishes the “in-order-to motive” of one’s action. By contrast, one’s “because motives” consist in the environmental, historical factors that influenced the (now past) decision to embark upon the project and that can only be discovered by investigating in the “pluperfect tense,” that is, exploring those past factors that preceded that past decision.

Schutz’s distinctions here are relevant to contemporary debates about whether freedom is compatible with determinism since from the perspective of the lived in-order-to motive, one experiences oneself as free and morally responsible, but from the perspective of examining one’s because motives after completing one’s action, one correlates, as an observer of oneself, the choice of the project with its historical determinants. Of course, Schutz, working within the parameters of Husserl’s non-naturalistic account of consciousness, would have conceived such determinants not so much as empirico-mechanical causes but rather as influences discoverable through an interpretive process, associating earlier events with the later ones they seem to have influenced. Schutz’s position comes closest to the roughly compatibilist outlooks of P.F. Strawson and Thomas Nagel, who distinguish between the participant and observer attitudes prior to theoretical discussions and who align the participant attitude with freedom and the observer attitude with determinism. Schutz, however, contributes the unique insight that these attitudes take place within distinctive temporal frameworks, oriented toward the future or the past.

Schutz’s account of the temporal framework of motivation permitted criticism of Weber’s view that one could orient one’s action to the past behavior of others, since, while such behavior might have served as the because motive of an action, one could not aim at affecting another’s already completed action. Similarly, failure to appreciate temporality often leads to misinterpretations of action, as when one assumes that the outcome of an act may have been its motive without considering the actor’s in-order-to motive, which due to unforeseen events may have been adjusted or may have led to results contrary to those intended. Likewise, one can interpret an economic action after the fact as less than rational without taking sufficient account of the limited information that was available to the actor at the time of deciding to act and that might make her action seem perfectly rational. Moreover, the fact that one’s own temporal stream of consciousness never completely coincides with that of another, whose sequence of events and intensity of experience inevitably differs from one’s own, places limits on one’s understanding of another. As a consequence, the objective meanings of language, defined in dictionaries as invariant regardless of users, also bear subjective connotations for language users due to their unique histories of linguistic experience, even though for practical purposes of communication they are able to set aside such differences. For instance, one would have to consider in depth Goethe’s works as a whole to understand what he meant by “demonic.” Schutz’s basic point in all these examples involves getting behind constituted meanings to the temporal processes by which actors build up the meaning of their own actions—a meaningful build-up accentuated by the German title of his Phenomenology of the Social World (Der sinnhafte Aufbau der sozialen Welt).

In addition to this account of consciousness, motivation, and action, he examined the structure of the social world, including Consociates who share the same time and spatial access to each other’s bodies, Contemporaries with whom one shares only the same time, and Predecessors and Successors with whom one does not share the same time and to whose lived bodies one lacks access. Consociates, present to each other physically, partake of each other’s inner time, that is, the on-rolling life of the other, grasp the building up of the other’s experience, and live in a We-relationship that entails “growing older together.” While Consociates revise their types of each other immediately, one must proceed more inferentially with Contemporaries, Predecessors, and Successors, constructing ideal types based on letters or reports and running greater risks of misunderstanding, depending on the degree of anonymity of the person to be understood. One could say, then, that Weber’s method of ideal type construction, illustrated in his sociological account of the Protestant at the origins of capitalism, is not really that foreign to the everyday life-world in which actors beyond the Consociate level continually relate to each other via such type construction. Human actors in everyday life already adopt toward each other the attitudes of social scientists.

Schutz conceived his work as developing a “phenomenological psychology” of “inner experience” and focusing on the invariant features of the life-world toward which theoreticians, including social scientists, turn reflectively. Although Jürgen Habermas criticizes Schutz’s account of the life-world for being “abridged in a culturalistic fashion” and not addressing institutional orders and personality structures (Habermas 1987, 2:126–132), it would seem that Schutz himself delimits his own work in just this fashion. According to him, social scientists develop constructs, ideal types, of the meaning-contexts of life-world actors, and they test these types to determine if they are causally adequate, that is conforming to past experience, and meaning adequate, that is, consistent with whatever else is known about the actor. Responding to Mises’s critique that Weber’s ideal-types are too historically specific, Schutz suggested that the later Weber’s ideal types in Economy and Society attain a generality comparable to that of Mises’ own economic theory, which itself could be interpreted as presenting ideal-typical descriptions of the behavior of economic agents. The later Weber’s types depict the invariant subjective experiences of anyone who acts within the economic framework as defined by the principle of marginal utility, that is, choosing to maximize satisfaction.

3. Extensions

3.1 The Bergson Writings

Schutz’s manuscripts on Bergson, produced from 1925 to 1927 and finally published in English in 1982, illuminate his subsequent works, with which they share the general purpose of “the grounding of the social sciences in the Thou experience.” (Schutz 1982, 34) In reaction to positivistic approaches of the Schlick Circle (in which Felix Kaufmann participated) that reduced experience to what the method of natural scientific observation found tolerable, Schutz sought to give an account of the life-form of pre-scientific experience preceding conceptual-categorical comprehension, the “highest and most powerful life-form” (Schutz 1982, 53). Of course, by moving in this direction, he encountered the problem, faced by Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Wilfrid Sellars, John McDowell, Robert Brandom, and others, namely, how it is possible to access the pre-conceptual without conceptualizing it. Hence, he acknowledged that his work is “in conflict with its material” since it “is forced to resort to conceptual formulations” (Schutz 1982, 70). This problem parallels the problem of reaching the life-form of the present unfolding of experience (duration) since one can only speak of it by arresting its flow, distinguishing its moments, and thus remembering what has lapsed—but then one is in the new life-form of memory. Although this gap between present duration and memory prompted his turn to Husserlian phenomenology, the problematic itself highlighted for him the pervasiveness and hiddenness of interpretive activity as one moves between interpretive frameworks—a principal theme of all his later work. He took notice of this theme when he frequently pointed out how one’s reconstitution of a past experience in memory varied according to the interests of the present from which one remembered the past. Indeed a favorite example from Bergson’s work involved an actor reflecting upon a prior process of choosing and interpreting it as if it had been a choice between two clearly defined possibilities, whereas in fact the process often oscillated between several options, retaining, reproducing, comparing, and modifying them in succession. In general, Schutz concurred with Bergson on such notions such as attention to life, planes of consciousness, the body as the intersection of outer and inner temporality, music as the model of duration, and multiple types of ordering, but rejected his bio-evolutionary theory, vitalism, and the idea of a supra-personal elán.

3.2 The Social Sciences

Although Schutz defended Weber against Mises, he agreed with many basic premises of Mises and the Austrian tradition that focused on the subjective preferences of the purchaser conferring value on objects instead of explaining value as the result of objective processes such as production costs or labor time invested. He also shared Mises’s suppositions about value-freedom in economic science, the need to describe rather than evaluate preferences, and the instrumental task of science, namely, of showing how to achieve ends rather than assessing their value. Since Mises considered all acting economic insofar as any consumer choice involved maximizing satisfaction in the widest sense, he opposed the narrow type of the homo economicus, modeled on the businessperson driven solely by economic motives at the expense of all others. Schutz, however, posited the life-world with its wide diversity of motivations at the base of economic theory. He conceived such theory as adopting a reflective perspective governed by the principle of marginal utility, namely, that ideal types ought to be constructed as if all actors “had oriented their life-plans to realize the greatest utility with minimal cost.” (Schutz 1964, 87) Besides thus resuscitating a version of homo economicus, Schutz insisted that economists study purposive-rational actions, which, in Weber’s sense, involved a reflective comparison of alternative projects before adopting one as an in-order-to motive. In addition, he classified the sense of uneasiness that Mises described as prompting the search for satisfaction under the category of because motives; one first adopts an rationally determined economic project and in retrospect discovers the preceding dissatisfaction. To understand the difference between conceiving all action as economic and conceiving economic action as one type of action within an more encompassing life-world, one might compare Mises with Schutz with reference to a problem raised within contemporary discussions of collective action, namely, how traditional non-economic values (e.g., those of politics or ethics) ought to intersect the market. Mises would countenance economic agents registering their values economically, that is, by deciding to purchase or not (e.g. as a protest against polluting companies), thereby converting all values into economic ones, whereas Schutz would call for a process negotiating the boundaries between different life-world value domains.

In “Concept and Theory Formation in the Social Sciences,” Schutz addressed the broader issue of the relationship between philosophy and the social sciences in general. In that essay, Schutz responded to Ernest Nagel’s positivistic view that the social sciences should make use of natural scientific methods, identifying evidence with sensory observable data and criticizing the Weberian method of “understanding” as appealing to uncontrollable and unverifiable introspection. Schutz agreed with Nagel on several counts, namely that social scientists needed to validate theoretical beliefs, that lack of predictability in the social sciences did not disqualify their scientific character, and that Weber would have been wrong if his method of “subjective interpretation” implied empathy with unobservable, introspective states. The problem was, though, that the natural scientific approach to the social sciences, insofar as it separated verifiable observable behavior from unverifiable inner states (purposes, emotions), seemed to play on the map drawn by Descartes who divorced body from mind and allowed only statements about the former to be scientifically verifiable. Further, the natural scientific approach depended on a basic presupposition since without first examining the object of social science—social reality, in Schutz’s terms—one would be simply presupposing that the methods of the natural sciences were appropriate to its study. Therefore, Schutz attempted first to clarify social reality, described in depth by his own phenomenology of the social world, and to indicate how actors sustain that reality by understanding each other’s in-order-to motives in typical terms (e.g., going to school, making a purchase, marrying). Such mutual understanding takes place without either somehow or other penetrating into the other’s private, inner sanctum, or reducing the other to the status of animal organism responding to stimuli. Given this account of social reality, in which actors give meaning to their world, as opposed to physical reality whose objects (e.g., electrons, quarks) do not interpret their world, Schutz argued that the appropriate social scientific method involved developing constructs of everyday actor’s constructs. Social scientific constructs, ideal types in Weber’s sense, aimed at capturing the subjective meaning of the actor, that is, according to Weber’s intentions, the meaning of the actor as opposed to the social scientist and not some introspective inner process. Schutz conceived statistical and other formulations of social scientific laws as a legitimate kind of intellectual shorthand, always presupposing the meaningful activity of the individual social actor, the “forgotten man” of the social sciences (Schutz 1964, 6–7). To ensure the kind of validation that Nagel sought, mistakenly though, by restricting himself to sensory observable data, Schutz proposed that social scientists displace their everyday practical interests in favor of a guiding interest in accurate scientific description and observe postulates of logical consistency and adequacy to the experiences described.

In order to elucidate the meaning of rational action, Schutz hypothesized what a rational actor would have to know, even though such completely rational actions might never be realized in everyday life. Such an actor would have to know: an end’s relationship with other ends, the consequences and by-products of realizing an end, the means suitable for the end, the interaction of such means with other ends and means, and the accessibility of those means. In addition, the rational actor would need to understand: her interactors’ understanding of all the previous factors, the interpretation of her act by others, the reactions of other people and their motivation, and the useful categories she had already discovered in the social world. Although social scientists might use such models of completely rational action to assess the rationality of everyday actors, Schutz cautioned social scientists that if their task were to describe life-world actors, they also needed to be wary of replacing the viewpoint of everyday actors with a fictional, non-existing world constructed by scientific observers. In fact, a central point of discussion in the published correspondence between Schutz and Talcott Parsons concerned the subjective viewpoint of the actor, whose sub-acts, for example, could not be adequately understood without comprehending the actor’s overarching project, whose temporal span is at first accessible only to that actor. Finally, it should be noted that Schutz himself produced two pieces of applied research in which he constructed ideal types of the Stranger and the Homecomer, taking account of what their experiences meant to them instead of what social scientists or others might think they meant.

3.3 Other Philosophies

Although references to philosophers in the pragmatist tradition, such as John Dewey and George Herbert Mead are scattered through Schutz’s writings, it was to William James that he devoted his first full-length essay after arriving in the United States. Briefly alluding to the methodological differences between Husserl and James, he emphasized two points where the “great masters” converged: the stream of thought and the theory of fringes. Both thinkers stressed that personal consciousness involves no multiplicity of elements needing to be reunited, but rather a unity from which one separates out components, and they each examined the modifications that reflection introduces into the lived stream, converting an “I” into a “Me” or uncovering the workings of intentionality. Further, Husserl’s idea that the kernel of meaning distinguishing an object stood out against the unthematized network of relationships that makes up its horizon paralleled James’s belief that topics have their “fringes.” Such fringes connect a topic with other experiences, such that, for instance, one does not hear merely “thunder,” but “thunder-breaking-in-upon-silence-and-contrasting-with-it.” Similarly, the Jamesian idea about grasping as a unity what must be learned through a many-stepped processes, such as the Pythagorean theorem, could be translated into the Husserlian terminology regarding the monothetical grasping of polythetic processes. Likewise, James’s discussion of focusing on an object within a broader topic resembled Husserl’s view that one could discern a noema, that is, a perspectival aspect through which a thing constituted of many such aspects presented itself.

Another American philosopher to whom Schutz dedicated an entire essay was George Santayana, whose Dominations and Powers he reviewed. While most of the essay was expository, Schutz praised Santayana’s effort to base politics on a philosophical anthropology and his insights into the enslaving potential of technology. However, Schutz, no doubt convinced by Mises’s positive assessment of economic activity, resisted Santayana’s reduction of it to domination. Likewise, as a phenomenologist opposed to a Santayana’s naturalistic founding of spirit on the physical order of nature, Schutz dissented from a conviction derived from this naturalism, namely, that democracy could solve it problems only by returning to the “generative order” of agriculture.

Besides these interchanges with American philosophers, Schutz (later in his career) interpreted the work of Max Scheler and (earlier) engaged thoroughly his treatment of intersubjectivity, a topic that Schutz insisted was to be treated within the natural attitude, in which one never doubted the existence of others. Schutz agreed with Scheler’s belief that the “We” is given prior to the “I”—a position that the latter defended on the basis of the psychology of children and cultures less accustomed to self-reflection. Schutz supported this priority, however he did so on the grounds that while living in one’s acts in the natural attitude and living also in the other’s present experience as it unfolds, one at first does not clearly distinguish one’s own thoughts from others’. Nevertheless, as soon as one reflects on his own stream of consciousness—and children and cultures may develop this capacity for self-reflection later—he becomes aware that his experiences are his own. Schutz found plausible Scheler’s belief in the inner (indubitable) perception of the other, if “inner perception” refers to anything connected with mental life or if one locates the experience of living in the vivid simultaneity of the “We” within his own conscious stream, as Schutz believed possible. However much in that vivid simultaneity one might be unable to doubt the other’s existence, one could still be mistaken about specific thoughts of the others, since by belonging to the other’s stream of consciousness these thoughts share the dubitability characterizing outer perceptions, likewise transcendent to one’s stream of experience.

Another figure, more or less within the phenomenological tradition, whose views on intersubjectivity Schutz examined and criticized, was Jean-Paul Sartre, particularly the Sartre of Being and Nothingness. In “Sartre’s Theory of the Alter Ego,” Schutz elucidated Sartre’s attempt to develop an extra-empirical, real communication with the other that avoids the extremes of an empiricist intersubjectivity beginning with the other’s body and an idealist reduction of the other to a series of presentations. After explaining Sartre’s differences regarding intersubjectivity with Husserl, Hegel, and Heidegger, Schutz laid out Sartre’s existential account of how the other is given as a subject through the Look and how one can in turn objectify the other by returning the gaze. Although Sartre had intended to describe how one’s body is given to the other, he instead portrayed how the other’s body is given to oneself, assuming that such descriptions were reversible. Schutz, who did not believe that the problem of intersubjectivity could be addressed adequately within the transcendental sphere, applauded Sartre’s rejection of Husserl’s transcendental approach to intersubjectivity; however, Sartre’s emphasis on the other as a center of activity reflected a continuing Husserlian influence. The main problem, though, with Sartre’s doctrine was that its starting point in a mutual looking, by which each subject reduces the other to an object, precluded any possibility of a relationship between the I-subject and other-subject. Further, Schutz wondered how Sartre would know that the other’s body was given to him in the same way that his body was to the other if the other’s subjectivity escaped his “I.” Moreover, Schutz acknowledged that the other’s interests might not coincide with his own, but he failed to see how this fact entailed that either the other or he reduce each other to a utensil. Instead, he pointed to the “mutual tuning-in” to be found in making music together and in language as proof that subjects interact as “co-performing subjectivities” and that mutual interaction in freedom better describes intersubjectivity than Sartre’s practical solipsism.

3.4 Applications

In 1945, Schutz published an essay, “On Multiple Realities,” that extended the theory of The Phenomenology of the Social World and anticipated later essays applying that theory. While he reiterated earlier views about levels of activity, Bergsonian tensions of consciousness, and the structure of the social world, his work took a decidedly pragmatic twist, emphasizing “working” (Wirken) as involving bodily movements as opposed to the covert performances of mere thinking. In manuscripts in the 1930s and after The Phenomenology of the Social World, Schutz had already turned in this pragmatic direction. In “On Multiple Realities,” he enlarged upon the “world of working” by demonstrating how reflection dissolves the self unified in lived action into partial, role-taking selves and by expanding Mead’s idea of the “manipulatory sphere” to include worlds within “potential reach,” either restorable (from the past) or attainable (in the future). This “world of working” constitutes the paramount reality, organized in its interests in the face of the fundamental anxiety that derives, as it did for Heidegger, from the inescapability of one’s own death. Following Husserl’s views on how consciousness can modify its stances toward reality and de-ontologizing James’s sub-universes of reality, Schutz developed the notion of various finite provinces of meaning. One enters any of these provinces, such as those of phantasms, dreams, the theater, religious experience, or theoretical contemplation, by undergoing different types of epoché, analogous to the phenomenological prototype, as when one slips into a daydream, falls asleep, watches theater curtains open, commences a ritual, or assumes the scientist’s role. Each province contains its distinctive logical, temporal, corporal, and social dimensions, and movement between the provinces only becomes paradoxical (e.g., asking how phenomenologists are able to communicate their private findings publicly) if one conceives the provinces as ontological static realms to which one transmigrates as a soul to another world. Rather the provinces are permeable, and one adopts the attitudes of scientist or religious believer within the world of working as if it were seen through by another viewpoint, all the while that its communicative activities subtend these other provinces. There is something paradoxical, though, about describing one’s dreams or theorizing about religious experience since to give an account one must absent oneself from the province for which one accounts, and Kierkegaard’s notion of indirect communication and various postmodern critiques of theory address themselves to just such paradoxes.

The essay on multiple realities underpins Schutz’s theory of signs and symbols in “Symbol, Reality, and Society,” published almost ten years later. Synthesizing the notion of potential reach from the earlier essay with Husserl’s concept of appresentation, namely that one element of a pair refers to another not directly given in experience, Schutz describes how agents overcome whatever transcends them. Hence they leave marks to bring within reach what they leave behind (e.g., breaking a twig to remind oneself to turn when one returns) or follow indications, that is, regular connections not of their making (e.g. smoke indicating a not yet visible fire), to bring within their knowledge what lies beyond it. Signs, however, appresent in an intersubjective setting the meanings of one person to another, but an insuperable transcendence still remains insofar as the each one’s stream of consciousness and therefore meanings are never identical with another’s. Finally, through symbols, developed within groups, something given within everyday reality appresents a reality belonging to a entirely different province of meaning, an ultimate transcendence (e.g., the stone where Jacob dreamed of a ladder to heaven memorializes God, accessible within the religious province of meaning).

Schutz dealt with this theme of language in other contexts, comparing Husserl’s distinction between prepredicative (prepropositional) and predicative levels with Kurt Goldstein’s separation, based on studies of brain lesions, of a concrete attitude relying on automatic speech associations from an abstract attitude forming propositions and utilizing rational language. Husserl’s prepredicative/predicative differentiation plays a key role in Schutz’s essay “Type and Eidos in Husserl’s Late Philosophy,” in which he shows a gradual development from empirical types passively constituted within the prepredicative sphere to presumptive universals spontaneously formed in the predicative sphere. At the predicative level, scientific reflection further transforms nonessential types (e.g., that whales are fish) into essential ones (whales are mammals), and philosophy seeks eidetic universals. At the end of this essay, Schutz speculates whether the Husserlian method of freely varying examples to determine the essential features that survive through such variations is not constrained by both ontological structure (e.g., sounds are not colors) and the socially shaped, natural-attitude experience of types. In his essay “Tiresias, or our Knowledge of Future Events,” produced contemporaneously with the type essay, Schutz explains how knowledge based on natural attitude types functions in contrast to the mythical Tiresias’ knowledge of the future, which is private and detached from his present or past experience. These types, based on past experiences or socially transmitted, aim at future occurrences not in their uniqueness but with an emptiness that future events will fill in, such that only in retrospect, after an event occurs, is one able to determine how much that event was expected or unexpected. Finally, there are future events lying beyond one’s influence that one expects only to conform with past experience and there are indeterminate projects that provide direction—not too tightly, though—as one gives shape to what is within one’s power.

Schutz, himself a trained pianist and widely read musicologist, integrated his phenomenology with his understanding of music. Music, differing from language in being non-representative, lends itself to phenomenological analysis in the meaning it carries beyond its mere physical nature as sound waves and in its character as an ideal object that must be constituted through its unfolding stages, i.e., polythetically. Further music is bound to inner temporality, and its themes, even though their note sequences are the same, vary according to context, require reflection for their recognition, and emerge through an interplay between musical elements and the listener’s attention and interest. Schutz found music instructive in regard to social relationships insofar as, prior to any communication, parties to musical performances establish a non-linguistic, non-conceptual “mutual tuning in relationship.” This “tuning-in,” this sharing of another’s flux of experience in inner time already described in his Phenomenology, is very clearly exhibited whenever a listener to a musical performance participates in quasi-simultaneity in the composer’s stream of consciousness or when co-performers orient themselves to each other, the composer, and the audience. Hence, Schutz disagreed with Maurice Halbwachs who posited musical notation as the basis of social relationships between performers, when in fact it is merely a technical device accidental to their relationship. In another essay, Schutz depicted Mozart as a social scientist, presenting a succession of situations that different characters interpret, and Schutz showed how orchestral representations of characters and their moods in melody made possible a simultaneity of fluxes of inner time that the non-operatic, non musical dramatist could only unfold successively. Without self-consciously philosophizing, Mozart conveyed in music and better than most philosophers in their own medium, how human beings meet each other as a “We.”

Fred Kersten discovers in Schutz’s musical writings important philosophical insights. For instance, music and inner time unfold polythetically and cannot be grasped monothetically; that is, one must live through the unfolding of a symphony or inner experience, and any conceptual summary of their contents inevitably fails to do justice to their meaning. However, since all conceptualization consists in a monothetical grasping of polythetic stages, Schutz is actually realizing that certain dimensions of consciousness elude conceptualization and thus demarcating the limits of rationalization, just as he had pointed out how certain provinces of meaning (e.g. dreams) evade theoretic comprehension or duration eludes memory. According to Kersten, Schutz has seen clearly that the passive associations of listening (e.g. recognizing the appearance of symphonic theme) differ from those of sight (e.g., apprehending an object like a house) and that listening does not identify numerically distinct items but produces an illusion of identification. Schutz’s conclusion that sameness in music involves not numerical unity but recurrent likeness challenges the fundamental Husserlian thesis that the synthesis of passive identification is universal, at the basis of the constitution of the world.

Schutz was also a master of literature, a careful student of the works of Goethe, and author of an article that analyzed Miguel de Cervantes’s Don Quixote through the prism of the theory of multiple realities. Cervantes repeatedly brings Quixote’s “world of chivalry”—an order of reality with its arguments for its own reality, its stock of knowledge, modes of social reinforcement, and views about space, time, and causality—into conflict with the worlds of drama, common sense, and science. Although Quixote is capable of constructing a defense of his own chivalrous world from within that world, the fact that this phantasied world contains an enclave of dreams (at the cave of Montesinos) ends up undermining it by raising the possibility that it itself is but a dream. Quixote’s withdrawal of the accent of reality from his private province of meaning reveals for Schutz the importance of the paramount reality of everyday life and the value of Sancho Panza who “remains deeply rooted in the heritage of common sense.” (Schutz 1964, 158)

Schutz also brought his phenomenology to bear on political issues such as citizenship or racial equality. His essay “The Well-Informed Citizen,” dealing not only with citizenship but also the sociology of knowledge under the rubric of the social distribution of knowledge, constructs ideal types of the expert, the man on the street, and the well-informed citizen (to whom it falls to determine which experts are competent). Schutz delineates various zones of interests, or relevances, extending from those within reach to those absolutely irrelevant, comments on the constant changeability of relevance configurations, and differentiates between relevances intrinsic to a theme, which one chooses, and those imposed. Paradoxically, as modernity’s rationalization processes heighten anonymity, modern technology also brings everyone within reach, as the nuclear arms race demonstrates, and Schutz suggests as a solution that citizens become broadly informed rather than succumb to the narrow dogmatism of the man on the street or the short-sighted specialization of experts. In becoming well-informed, one depends on knowledge socially derived through the consultation of eyewitnesses, insiders, analysts, and commentators, depending on their access to facts and governing relevances, much as Alvin Goldman’s social epistemology involves appraising the ‘veritistic’ value of assorted agents’ claims and practices. Schutz, usually the value-free describer of social reality, in his conclusion endorses a normative notion of democracy in which it is a duty and a privilege, frequently not available in non-democratic societies, for well-informed citizens to express and defend opinions that often conflict with the uninformed opinions of the man in the street.

Schutz composed “Equality and the Meaning Structure of the Social World” at the time of the legal decision of Brown v. Board of Education that ended racially segregated education in the United States. With typical dispassion, Schutz explains how the meaning of the term “equality” depends on the domain of relevances to which it pertains (e.g., economic equality, equality of civil rights, etc.) and on the in-group or out-group utilizing it—and here he conceives interpretation in terms of groups rather than individuals. He spends most of the essay contrasting subjective and objective interpretations of group membership, equality, and equality of opportunity, construing “subjective” and “objective” in terms of in-group and out-group interpretations. As regards group membership, he illustrates that the mere categorization of another as a member of a group need not be discriminatory, but depends upon an appropriate evaluation of the category from the viewpoint of the categorized individual. In-groups and out-groups differ in whether they understand equality merely as “formal,” i.e., as nondiscrimination, or “real,” calling for special rights and services. Similarly groups think of equality of opportunity from an out-group perspective as “the career open to all” without appreciating how in-group members might subjectively experience insuperable obstacles in trying to avail themselves of opportunities supposedly objectively equal. In this essay, Schutz is concerned not to present a final definition of equality, but to highlight the differences between in-group and out-group understandings that serve as the preconditions of any discussion about it.

Some recently published texts that Schutz authored during an ethics institute in 1956 make possible an even richer awareness of his views on politics. In these documents, he recognizes the complex, unforeseen consequences resulting from social change, urges active engagement with others as crucial for developing social and civil judgment, and examines the barriers to sound civil judgment created by government, political parties, pressure organizations, mass media, and educational, familial, religious, and professional institutions. At one point, he even criticizes views that limit democracy to mere majoritarian rule insofar as they neglect the importance of the single individual’s ability “to make his personal opinion be heard and appreciated,” preferably in smaller publics, such as families, schools, local communities (cited in L. Embree 1999, 271). One could take Schutz’s thoughts here to converge with political theories favoring what is today known as deliberative democracy. Moreover, his normative judgment against implementations of democracy that increase the anonymity of citizens suggests that a parallel normative, even ethical, dimension informs his many theoretic endeavors to retrieve from anonymity the neglected subjective viewpoint of actors, whether strangers, homecomers, victims of discrimination, or the “forgotten man” of social sciences.

3.5 Phenomenology

Schutz’s philosophical targeting of the social world had its repercussions upon phenomenology, particularly in his critique near the end of his career of Husserl’s account (also referred to as a “transcendental constitution”) of how the other person comes to appearance in consciousness. In “The Problem of Transcendental Intersubjectivity in Husserl,” Schutz first objected when Husserl in his Fifth Cartesian Mediation prepared the ground for the other’s appearance in consciousness by the methodology of screening off everything that referred to other minds. Husserl had begun the Cartesian Meditations by reflectively abstaining from believing in the existence of what appeared in experience in order to refrain from any dogmatic suppositions, but since this first epoché, or phenomenological reduction, still left meanings with intersubjective references, the screening off methodology, or second epoché, became necessary. For Husserl, one’s actual or potential experiences of correlates that were not properly of the ego still would belong to one’s sphere of ownness, but one had to seek to exclude any reference those correlates, as products of the sense-determining of other subjectivities, might have to those other subjectivities. For Schutz, however, insofar as those experiences of what was not properly of the ego, supposedly confined within the sphere of ownness, had their origin in the intersubjective world of everyday life that higher level phenomenological reflection presupposed, it seemed difficult to see how one could exclude from such correlates any reference to the sense-determininng of other subjectivities. It was as though Husserl was striving for a theoretical detachment that the ontological origins of theory would not allow. In addition, for Schutz the very consciousness of another inevitably instituted a relationship with her. Husserl’s argument in the Fifth Meditation continued by affirming that a non-ratiocinative “pairing” occurred through which one transferred the sense “another living body” to another. One could then verify that the other’s living body was like one’s own if it continued manifesting behavior congruent with what one would expect of a living body. Schutz challenged this sense-transfer, however, since one experienced the other’s body from the outside, unlike one’s own, which was given interiorly (but might the similarities suffice for the transfer?), and he suggested that verification through what was “congruent” behavior drew on social-world presuppositions of how bodies ought to behave. Finally, he questioned whether the philosopher, refraining from belief in the existence of the world or others and entering into a certain reflective solitude, could ever experience the transcendental community of which Husserl spoke, since she only constituted the world for herself and not for all other transcendental egos. Intersubjectivity, Schutz concluded, was a matter of everyday life to be simply described and not to be constituted within the transcendental sphere of a self-reflective consciousness giving an account of how the other comes to appearance. Just as Schutz had argued that the social world dictated the methods for its own social scientific investigation, so here it seemed to prescribe to phenomenology the approach appropriate to its description.

In the last thirteen years of his life, Schutz was preparing a comprehensive phenomenology of the natural attitude, and one manuscript, edited by Richard Zaner, was posthumously published as Reflections on the Problem of Relevance, and another, co-authored by Thomas Luckmann, appeared as The Structures of the Life World. The former book distinguishes different sets of interests, or relevances: topical (which focus attention on themes), interpretive (which confer meanings on experiences or objects), and motivational. Such relevances often involve a subject, with more or less systematic interests, or relevances, interacting with the world, and from this interaction between subject and world, it becomes evident what is “of relevance” to an actor. These relevances, interdependent on each other and conjoined with one’s system of types or categories, constitute a stock of knowledge, which Schutz examines in terms of its genesis and structure. He further explores the meaning of one’s biographical situation, including types and relevances, one’s body, and the ontological constraints of space and time that, for instance, prevent one from being at certain places at certain times or compel one to wait (for salt to dissolve in water).

The Structures of the Life-World represents a most complex and thorough restatement of many of the themes Schutz addressed throughout his life. After a more general account of the life-world and its relation to the sciences, the book takes up its various stratifications, such as provinces of meaning, temporal and spatial zones of reach, and social structure. Schutz and Luckmann then comment on the components of one’s stock of knowledge, including learned and non-learned elements, relevances and types, and trace the build-up of such a stock. The authors study the social conditioning of one’s subjective stock of knowledge and inquire about the social stock of knowledge of a group and different possible combinations of knowledge distribution (generalized and specialized). They consider how subjective knowledge becomes embodied in a social stock of knowledge and how the latter influences the former. In addition, the authors pursue such issues as the structures of consciousness and action, the choosing of projects, rational action, and forms of social action, whether such action be unilateral or reciprocal, immediate or mediate. A final section analyzes the boundaries of experience, different degrees of transcendencies (from simply bringing an object within reach to the experience of death), and the mechanisms for crossing boundaries (e.g. symbols).

4. The Schutzian Tradition

In the years after Schutz’s death in 1959, his works have been posthumously published and his thought expanded in several directions. Peter Berger and Thomas Luckmann wrote The Social Construction of Reality, which focused on how subjective human processes construct objective structures that human subjectivity in turn interprets and reacts to and which was among the most widely read books of social science in the twentieth century. Ilja Srubar emphasized the importance of the pragmatic dimensions of Schutz’s corpus, just as Hans-Georg Soeffner, along with Jochen Dreher, has developed its symbolic aspects. On Schutzian grounds, Lester Embree produced a theory of science in the model of a Wissenschaftslehre, and George Psathas extended Schutz’s thought in the direction of ethnomethodology and conversation analysis. Recently, sociologists Hubert Knoblauch and Carlos Belvedere have shown the relevance of Schutz’s framework to communication theory and questions of social ontology, respectively. The Austrian Economic School has continued to make use of Schutz’s works, as Daniela Griselda López has shown. López and Dreher have further argued that Schutzian theory can adequately account for the exercise of institutional power through the interplay between objective structures and subjective meaning-interpretation and the idea of relevances that are imposed upon agents. Michael Staudigl and George Berguno have edited a collection of essays on the connection between the Schutzian approach and various hermeneutic traditions. And Staudigl and Michael Barber have highlighted the connections between Schutz’s philosophy of multiple realities and religion and humor. Furthermore, collections of essays have addressed the value of Schutz’s paradigm for music, literature, and the arts. The work of Alfred Schutz opens a wide field that is fruitful for addressing multiple themes and underpinning and supporting multiple disciplines.

In 2016, the scholarly community in the Schutzian tradition commemorated both the passing of Thomas Luckmann, one of Schutz’s renowned students who developed his thought in diverse ways, and the fiftieth anniversary of the publication of The Social Construction of Reality. These commemorations took place through the editing of three major collections: Social Constructivism as Paradigm?, Lebenswelttheorie und Gesellschaftsanalyse, and Mathesis Universalis. While these works focus on Luckmann’s work, including The Structures of the Life-World that Luckmann co-authored with Schutz, several of the essays address aspects of Schutz’s thought: the objective dimensions of societal institutions in contrast to interpretations of such institutions as subjectivistic and devoid of power-relationships (Eberle 2019, Knoblauch 2019, Mijić 2018, Srubar 2019); the possibility of a communicative construction of reality (Knoblauch 2019); the Schutzian paradigm’s preservation of agents’ potential to resist societal control in contrast to Bourdieu’s account of habitus (Dreher 2019); the role of the body in We-relationships (Meyer 2018); the capacity of the Schutzian framework to account for resilience in the face of trauma (Endress 2021); inequality as imposed relevance (López 2021); space and bodiliness as pertinent to the life-world as protosociology (Mijić 2018, Dörfler & Rothfuss 2021, Steets 2021); degrees of freedom within Schutz’s relevance theory (Göttlich 2021); linkages between Schutz’s phenomenology and recent representatives of the Frankfurt School, such as Hartmut Rosa (Gros 2021, Wannenmacher 2021); and the role of the life-world as a mathesis universalis, that is, the ground-structure of all human experience that makes possible any comparison between cultures without reliance on the specific features of any one culture (Dreher 2021, Meyer 2021, Sebald 2009).

Bibliography

Works by Schutz

  • 1932, Der sinnhafte Aufbau der sozialen Welt: Eine Einleitung in die verstehenden Soziologie, Vienna: Springer (also in 1960) and Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1974; English translation: The Phenomenology of the Social World, G. Walsh and F. Lehnert (trans.), Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1967.
  • 1962, Collected Papers I: The Problem of Social Reality, Maurice Natanson (ed.), The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • 1964, Collected Papers II: Studies in Social Theory, Arvid Brodersen (ed.), The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • 1966, Collected Papers III: Studies in Phenomenological Philosophy, I. Schutz (ed.), The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • 1970, On Phenomenology and Social Relations: Selected Writings, H. Wagner (ed.), Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • 1971, Reflections on the Problem of Relevance, R.M. Zaner (ed.), New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • 1972, “Choice and the Social Sciences,” in Lester Embree (ed.), Life-World and Consciousness, Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 565–596.
  • 1973, (with T. Luckmann), The Structures of the Life-World, R.M. Zaner and T. Engelhardt (trans.), Evanston: Northwestern University Press, and London: Heinemann; German edition: Strukturen der Lebenswelt, vol. 1, Neuwied: Luchterhand, 1975; vol. 2: The Structures of the Life-World, R.M. Zaner and David J. Parent (trans.), Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1983; German edition: Strukturen der Lebenswelt, vol. 2, Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1984.
  • 1976, “Fragments on the Phenomenology of Music” in In Search of Musical Method, F.J. Smith (ed.), London, New York, and Paris: Gordon and Breach Science Publishers, 23–71.
  • 1978, (with T. Parsons), The Theory of Social Action: The Correspondence of Alfred Schutz and Talcott Parsons, R. Grathoff (ed.), Bloomington and London: Indiana University Press; German edition: Zur Theorie sozialen Handelns: Briefwechsel/Alfred Schutz, Talcott Parsons, Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1977.
  • 1982, Life Forms and Meaning Structure, H. Wagner (trans., ed.), London: Routledge and Kegan Paul; German edition: Theorie der Lebensformen, I. Srubar (ed.), Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1981.
  • 1989, (with A. Gurwitsch), Philosophers in Exile: The Correspondence of Alfred Schutz and Aron Gurwitsch, 1939–1959, R. Grathoff (ed.), J.C. Evans (trans.), Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.
  • 1996, Collected Papers IV, H. Wagner and G. Psathas (eds.), in collaboration with F. Kersten, Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  • 1997, “Positivistic Philosophy and the Actual Approach of Interpretative Social Science: An Ineditum of Alfred Schutz from Spring 1953,” L. Embree (ed.), Husserl Studies, 14: 123–149.
  • 1999, “Some Considerations concerning Thinking in Terms of Barriers,” “Memorandum (to Doctor Harold Lasswell),” “Report on the Discussions of Barrier to Equality of Opportunity for the Development of Power of Social and Civil Judgment,” “Letter of Alfred Schutz to Clarence H. Faust, The Fund for the Advancement of Education,” all in L. Embree, “The Ethical Political Side of Schutz: His Contributions at the 1956 Institute on Ethics concerned with Barriers to Equality of Opportunity,” in Schutzian Social Science, L. Embree (ed.), Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer Academic Publishing, 235–318.
  • 2003, Theorie der Lebenswelt 1: Die pragmatische Schichtung der Lebenswelt, M. Endress and I. Srubar (eds.), vol. 5,1: Alfred Schütz Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G. Soeffner, and I. Srubar (eds.), Redaction, M. Endress, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
  • 2003, Theorie der Lebenswelt 2: Die kommunikative Ordnung der Lebenswelt, H. Knoblauch, R. Kurt, and H-G. Soeffner (eds.), vol. 5,2: Alfred Schütz Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G. Soeffner, and I. Srubar (eds.); Redaction, M. Endress, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
  • 2004, (with Eric Voegelin), Eine Freundschaft, die ein Leben ausgehalten hat: Briefwechsel 1938–1959, G. Wagner and G. Weiss (eds.), Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH. Translated as A Friendship that Lasted a Lifetime: The Correspondence Between Alfred Schutz and Eric Voegelin, 2011, G. Wagner and G. Weiss (eds.), trans. W. Petropulos, Columbia: University of Missouri Press.
  • 2004, Der sinnhafte Aufbau der sozialen Welt: Eine Einleitung in die verstehende Soziologie, M. Endress and J. Renn (eds.), vol 2: Alfred Schütz Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G. Soeffner, and I. Srubar; Redaction, M. Endress (eds.), Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
  • 2004, Relevanz und Handeln 1: Zur Phänomenologie des Alltagswissens, E. List (ed.), vol. 6,1: Alfred Schütz Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G. Soeffner, and I. Srubar (eds.); Redaction, M. Endress, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
  • 2005, Philosophisch-phänomenologische Schriften 2: Studien zu Scheler, James, und Sartre, H. Kellner und J. Renn (eds.), vol. 3,2: Alfred Schütz Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G. Soeffner, and I. Srubar (eds.); Redaction, M. Endress, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
  • 2006, Sinn und Zeit: Frühe Wiener Arbeiten und Entwürfe, M. Michailow (ed.), vol. 1: Alfred Schütz Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G. Soeffner, and I. Srubar (eds.); Redaction, M. Endress/G. Sebald, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
  • 2009, Philosophisch-phänomenologische Schriften 1: Zur Kritik der Phänomenologie Edmund Husserls, G. Sebald (ed.) in collaboration with R. Grathoff and T. Michael; Redaction, G. Sebald, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
  • 2009, “Private Family Journal of First Trip to the United States of America,” Evelyn S. Lang (trans.), Schutzian Research, 1: 245–271.
  • 2009, “Understanding, Self-reflection, and Equality: Alfred Schutz’s Participation in the 1955 Conference on Science, Philosophy, and Religion,” ed. Michael Barber, Schutzian Research, 1: 273–291.
  • 2009, Philosophisch-phänomenologische Schriften 1: Zur Kritik der Phänomenologie Edmund Husserls, Gerd Sebald (ed.) based on preliminary work by Richard Grathoff and Michael Thomas, vol. 3,1: Alfred Schütz Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G. Soeffner, and I. Srubar (eds.); Redaction, M. Endress, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
  • 2010, Zur Methodologie der Sozialwissenschaften, Thomas S. Eberle, Jochen Dreher and Gerd Sebald (eds.), Vol 4: Alfred Schütz Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G. Soeffner, and I. Srubar (eds.); Redaction, M. Endress, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
  • 2010, “The Problem of Transcendental Intersubjectivity in Husserl (with Comments of Dorion Cairns and Eugen Fink),” Fred Kersten (trans.), Schutzian Research, 2: 9–51.
  • 2010, “Problems of a Sociology of Language”(Fall Semester, 1958), Fred Kersten (ed.), Schutzian Research, 2: 53–105.
  • 2011, Relevanz und Handeln 2: Fremdheit, Gesellschaftliches Wissen und politisches Handeln, Andreas Göttlich, Gerd Sebald and Jan Weyand (eds.), Vol. 6(2): Alfred Schütz Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G. Soeffner, and I. Srubar (eds.); Redaction, M. Endress, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
  • 2011, Collected Papers V. Phenomenology and the Social Sciences, Lester E. Embree (ed.), Dordrecht: Springer.
  • 2011, “Interview with Dr. Alfred Schutz,” (November 20, 1958 New York City), Interviewed Bettina Bien Greaves, Schutzian Research, 3: 23–30.
  • 2011, (with Eric Voegelin) A Friendship that Lasted a Lifetime: The Correspondence between Alfred Schuetz and Eric Voegelin, Gerhard Wagner and Gilbert Weiss (eds.), William Petropulos (trans), Columbia, Missouri: University of Missouri Press.
  • 2012, Collected Papers VI. Literary Reality and Relationships, Michael D. Barber (ed.), Dordrecht: Springer.
  • 2013, Schriften zur Literatur, Michael D. Barber and Jochen Dreher (eds.), Vol. 8: Alfred Schütz Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G. Soeffner, and I. Srubar (eds.); Redaction, M. Endress, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
  • 2013, “Fragment of a Phenomenology of Rhythm,” Gerd Sebald and Jasmin Schreyer (transcription, ed., & trans.), Schutzian Research, 5: 11–22.
  • 2016, Schriften zur Musik, Gerd Sebald and Andreas Georg Stascheit (eds.), Vol. 7, Alfred Schütz Werkausgabe, H-G. Soeffner and I. Srubar (eds.); Redaction, M. Endress, Cologne: Herbert von Halem Verlag.

Secondary Literature

  • Barber, M., 1989, Social Typifications and the Elusive Other: The Place of Sociology of Knowledge in Alfred Schutz’s Phenomenology, Lewisburg: Bucknell University Press and London and Toronto: Associated University Presses.
  • –––, 2004, The Participating Citizen: A Biography of Alfred Schutz, Albany: State University of New York Press.
  • –––, 2017, Religion and Humor as Emancipating Provinces of Meaning, Dordrecht: Springer.
  • Barber, M., and J. Dreher (eds.), 2014, The Interrelation of Phenomenology, Social Sciences and the Arts, Dordrecht: Springer.
  • Belvedere, C., 2016, “Lester Embree on Collective Subjects,” Schutzian Research, 9: 79–84.
  • Belvedere, C. and A. Gros, 2019, “The Phenomenology of Social Institutions in the Schutzian Tradition,” Schutzian Research, 11: 43–74.
  • Berger, P.L. and T. Luckmann, 1967, The Social Construction of Reality, Garden City, New York: Doubleday Anchor.
  • Bergson, H. 1889, Essai sur les données de la conscience, Paris: Félix Alcan; English translation: Time and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of Consciousness, trans. by F.L. Pogson, London: George Allen and Unwin, 1921.
  • Bernstein, R.J., 1976, The Restructuring of Social and Political Theory, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
  • Brandom, R., 1994, Making It Explicit, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
  • Cox, R.R., 1978, Schutz’s Theory of Relevance: A Phenomenological Critique, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Dörfler, T. and E. Rothfuss, 2021, “Sozialer Raum als vergessene Mathesis Universalis der Phänomenologie? Ein raum– und leibbezogene Perspektive auf die Strukturen der Lebenswelt,” in Mathesis Universalis, J. Dreher (ed.), Wiesbaden: Springer, 143–169.
  • Dreher, J., 2011, “Alfred Schutz,” The Wiley-Blackwell Companion to Major Social Theorists, Volume 1: Classical Social Theorists, G. Ritzer and J. Stepnisky (eds.), West Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell, 489–510.
  • –––, 2019, “Oblivion of power? The Social Construction of Reality and the (counter)-critique of Pierre Bourdieu,” in Social Constructivism as Paradigm?, M. Pfadenhauer and H. Knoblauch (eds.), London and New York: Routledge, 235–250.
  • –––, 2021, “Einleitung: Strukturen der Lebenswelt als mathesis universalis der Sozialwissenschaften,” in Mathesis Universalis, J. Dreher (ed.), Wiesbaden: Springer, 1–11.
  • ––– (ed.), 2021, Mathesis Universalis: Die Aktuelle Relevanz derStrukturen der Lebenswelt,” Wiesbaden: Springer.
  • Dreher, J., and D.G. López, 2014, Fenomenología del Poder, Bogotá: Ediciones USTA.
  • Dreher, J., and D.G. López, 2015, “Subjectivity and Power,” Human Studies, 38: 197–222.
  • Eberle, T.S., 1984, Sinnkonstitution in Alltag und Wissenschaft: Der Beitrag der Phänomenologie und die Methodologie der Sozialwissenschaften, Bern and Stuttgart: Paul Haupt.
  • –––, 2019, “Variations of Constructivism,” in Social Constructivism as Paradigm?, M. Pfadenhauer and H. Knoblauch (ed.), London and New York: Routledge, 131–151.
  • Embree, L. (ed.), 1988, Worldly Phenomenology: The Continuing Influence of Alfred Schutz On North American Human Science, Washington, D.C.: Center for Advanced Research in Phenomenology and University Press of America.
  • –––, 1999, “The Ethical-Political Side of Schutz: His Contributions at the 1956 Institute on Ethics concerned with Barriers to Equality of Opportunity,” in Schutzian Social Science, L. Embree (ed.), Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 235–318.
  • –––, 2013, Alfred Schutz’s “Sociological Aspect of Literature”, Dordrecht: Springer.
  • –––, 2015, The Schutzian Theory of the Cultural Sciences, Dordrecht: Springer.
  • ––– and M. Barber (eds.), 2017, The Golden Age of Phenomenology at the New School for Social Research, 1954–1973, Athens, Ohio: Ohio University Press.
  • Endress, M., 2006, Alfred Schütz, Konstanz: UVK.
  • –––, 2021, “Trauma: Schritte zu einer phänomenologisch–fundierten soziologischen Analyse,” in Mathesis Universalis, J. Dreher (ed.), Wiesbaden: Springer, 211–246.
  • Endress, M., G. Psathas, and H. Nasu (eds.), 2004, Explorations of the Life-World: Continuing Dialogues with Alfred Schutz, Dordrecht: Springer.
  • Endress, M., and A. Hahn (eds.), 2018, Lebenswelttheorie und Gesellschaftsanalyse: Studium zum Werk von Thomas Luckmann, Köln: Herbert van Halem.
  • Göttlich, A., 2021, “Lebenswelt—Diskurs—Relevanz: Die Relevanztheorie von Alfred Schütz als diskursanalytische Instrument,” in Mathesis Universalis, J. Dreher (ed.), Wiesbaden: Springer, 171–194.
  • Grathoff, R., 1989, Milieu und Lebenswelt, Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
  • –––, and B. Waldenfels, 1983, Sozialität und Intersubjektivität: Phänomenologische Perspektiven der Sozialwissenschaften im Umkreis von Aron Gurwitsch und Alfred Schütz, Munich: Wilhelm Fink.
  • Gros, A.E., 2021, “Die Beschleunigung der Lebenswelt: Alfred Schütz’ Beiträge zu einer Phänomenologie der spätmodernen Weltbeziehung,” in Mathesis Universalis, J. Dreher (ed.), Wiesbaden: Springer, 291–316.
  • Gurwitsch, A., 1979, Human Encounters in the Social World, A. Métraux (ed.) and F. Kersten (trans.), Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.
  • Habermas, J., 1987, The Theory of Communicative Action, 2 vols., trans. T. McCarthy, Boston: Beacon Press.
  • –––, 1988, On the Logic of the Social Sciences, S.W. Nicholsen and J. A. Stark (trans.), Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
  • Husserl, E., 1969, Formal and Transcendental Logic, trans. D.Cairns, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • –––, 1973, Cartesian Meditations, D. Cairns (trans.), The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • –––, 1973, Experience and Judgment: Investigations in a Genealogy of Logic, L. Landgrebe (ed.), J. S. Churchill and K. Ameriks (trans.), Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
  • –––, 1990, On the Phenomenology of the Consciousness of Internal Time (1893–1917), J.B. Brough (trans.), Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  • James, W., 1893, The Principles of Psychology, 2 volumes, New York: Henry Holt.
  • Kersten, F., 1976, “Preface” to “Fragments on the Phenomenology of Music” in In Search of Musical Method, F.J. Smith (ed.), London, New York, and Paris: Gordon and Breach Science Publishers, 6–22.
  • Knoblauch, H., 2013, “Alfred Schutz’s Theory of Communicative Action,” Human Studies, 36: 323–327.
  • –––, 2019, “From the Social to the Communicative Construction of Reality,” in Social Constructivism as Paradigm?, M. Pfadenhauer and H. Knoblauch (eds.), London and New York: Routledge, 275–291.
  • List, E. and I. Srubar (eds.), 1988, Alfred Schuütz : Neue Beiträge zur Rezeption seines Werkes, Amsterdam : Rodopi.
  • López, D. G., 2016, “The Epistemic Claim to the Life-world: Alfred Schutz and the Debates of the Austrian School of Economics,” The Review of Austrian Economics, 29: 177–203.
  • –––, 2021, “The Subjective Experience of Inequality in Everyday Life: Contributions of Alfred Schutz’s Phenomenological Sociology,” in Mathesis Universalis, J. Dreher (ed.), Wiesbaden: Springer, 195–210.
  • Luckmann, T., 1983, Life-World and Social Realities, London: Heinemann.
  • –––, 2007, Lebenswelt, Identität, und Gesellschaft, Konstanz: UVK.
  • McDowell, J., 1994, Mind and World, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
  • Meyer, C., 2018, “Die Leiblichkeit der Lebenswelt: Körper und vor-personale Socialität bei Thomas Luckmann und in kulturhistorischer Perspektive,” in Lebenswelttheorie und Gesellschaftsanalyse, M. Endress and A. Hahn (eds.), Köln: Herbert von Halem, 100–127.
  • –––, 2021, “Zwei anthropologische Universalien in protosoziologische Zugriff,” in Mathesis Universalis, J. Dreher (ed.), Wiesbaden: Springer, 113–142.
  • Mijić, Ana, 2018, “Persönliche Identität Revisited,” in Lebenswelttheori und Gesellschaftsanalyse, M. Endress and A. Hahn (eds.), Köln: Herbert von Halem, 158–219.
  • Mises, L. 1960, Epistemological Problems of Economics, G. Reisman (trans.), Princeton, N. J: Van Nostrand.
  • –––, 1966, Human Action: A Treatise on Economics, Chicago: H. Regnery Co..
  • Nasu, H., L. Embree, G. Psathas, and I. Srubar (eds.), 2009, Alfred Schutz and His Intellectual Partners, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
  • Natanson, M., 1986, Anonymity: A Study in the Philosophy of Alfred Schutz, Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press.
  • O’Neill, J., 1974, Making Sense Together: An Introduction to Wild Sociology, New York: Harper and Row.
  • Parsons, Talcott, 1968, The Structure of Social Action, 2 volumes, New York: The Free Press.
  • Pfandenhauer, M. and Knoblauch, H. (eds.), 2019, Social Constructivism as Paradigm?: The Legacy of The Social Construction of Reality, London and New York: Routledge.
  • Salice, A. and H.B. Schmid (eds.), 2016, The Phenomenological Approach to Social Reality: History, Concepts, Problems, Dordrecht: Springer.
  • Sanna, G.L., 2007, Realizzazione etica del sé in Alfred Schütz: Tra pragmatismo e fenomenologia, Rome: Armando.
  • Santayana, G., 1951, Dominations and Powers : Reflections on Liberty, Society, and Government, New York : C. Scribner’s Sons.
  • Sartre, J-P., 1956, Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology, H. Barnes (trans.), New York: Philosophical Library.
  • Scheler, M., 1954, The Nature of Sympathy, P. Heath (trans.), New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • Sebald, G., 2009, “Einleitung des Herausgebers,” in Alfred Schutz, Alfred Schütz Werkausgabe (Volume 3.1), Philosophische–phänomenologische Schriften: Zur Kritik der Phänomenologie Edmund Husserls, G. Sebald (ed.), Konstanz: UVK, 9–45.
  • Sellars, W., 1956, “Does Empirical Knowledge Have a Foundation?” in H. Feigl and M. Scriben (eds.), The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of Psychology and Psychoanalysis (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science: Volume 1), Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 293–300.
  • Soeffner, H.G., 1997, The World of Rituals: The Interpretation of Everyday Life, New Brunswick: Transaction Press.
  • Sprondel, W. M. and R. Grathoff (eds.), 1979, Alfred Schutz und die Idee des Alltags in den Sozialwissenschaften, Stuttgart: Ferdinand Enke.
  • Srubar, I., 1988, Kosmion, Die Genese der pragmatischen Lebenswelttheorie von Alfred Schütz und ihr anthropologischer Hintergrund, Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
  • –––, 2007, Phänomenologie und soziologische Theorie: Aufsätze zur pragmatischen Lebenswelttheorie, Wiesbaden: VS, Verlag für Socialwissenschaften/GWV Fachverlage GmbH.
  • –––, 2019,“Autogenesis and Autopoiesis: On the Emergence of Social Reality in Social and Radical Constructivism,” in Social Constructivism as Paradigm?, M. Pfandenhauer and H. Knoblauch (eds.), London and New York: Routledge, 207–215.
  • Staudigl, M., 2017, “Alfred Schutz and Phenomenology of Religion: Explorations into Ambiguous Territory,” Human Studies, 40: 491–499.
  • ––– and G. Berguno (eds.), 2014, Schutzian Phenomenology and Hermeneutic Traditions, Dordrecht: Springer.
  • Steets, S., 2021, “Die Dualität von Leib und die Strukturen der Lebenswelt,” in Mathesis Universalis, J. Dreher (ed.), Wiesbaden: Springer, 97–112.
  • Strassheim, J., 2016, “Type and Spontaneity: Beyond Alfred Schutz’s Theory of the Social World,” Human Studies, 39: 493–512.
  • Ten Have, P. and G. Psathas (eds.), 1995, Situated Order: Studies in the Social Organization of Talk and Embodied Activities (Studies in Ethnomethodology and Conversational Analysis: Number 3), Washington, D.C.: International Institute for Ethnometholodology and Conversation Analysis and University Press of America.
  • Thomason, B.C., 1983, Making Sense of Reification: Alfred Schutz and Constructionist Theory, London: Macmillan.
  • Vaitkus, S., 1983, How is Society Possible?, Dordrecht, Boston, and London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  • Voegelin, E., 1952, The New Science of Politics: An Introduction, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Wagner, H. R., 1983, Alfred Schutz: An IntellectualBiography, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • –––, with I. Srubar, 1983, A Bergsonian Bridge to Phenomenological Psychology, Edmonton: University of Alberta Press.
  • Waldenfels, B., 1971, Das Zwischenreich des Dialogs: Sozialphilosophische Untersuchungen in Anschluss an Edmund Husserl, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Wannenmacher, B., 2021, “Alfred Schütz’ ‘Strukturen der Lebenswelt’ und kritische Theorie: Auf die Suche nach Schnittstellung,” in Mathesis Universalis, J. Dreher (ed.), Wiesbaden: Springer, 271–290.
  • Webb, R.B., 1976, The Presence of the Past: John Dewey and Alfred Schutz on the Genesis and Organization of Experience, Gainesville: University Presses of Florida.
  • Weber, M., 1978, Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology, E. Fischoff, et al. (trans.), G. Roth and C. Wittich (eds.), 2 volumes, Berkeley: University of California Press.
  • –––, 1958, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, T. Parsons (trans.), New York: Scribners.
  • Williame, R., 1973, Les Fondements Phénoménologiques de la Sociologie Comprehénsive: Alfred Schutz et Max Weber, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Wolff, Kurt (ed.), 1984, Alfred Schutz: Appraisals and Developments, Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff.

Copyright © 2021 by
Michael Barber <michael.barber@slu.edu>

Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world-wide funding initiative.
The Encyclopedia Now Needs Your Support
Please Read How You Can Help Keep the Encyclopedia Free