Hiddenness of God

First published Sat Apr 23, 2016; substantive revision Fri Jul 8, 2022

“Divine hiddenness”, as the phrase suggests, refers, most fundamentally, to the hiddenness of God, i.e., the alleged fact that God is hidden, absent, or silent. In religious literature, there is a long history of expressions of annoyance, anxiety, and despair over divine hiddenness, so understood. For example, ancient Hebrew texts lament God’s failure to show up in experience or to show proper regard for God’s people or some particular person, and two Christian Gospels portray Jesus, in his cry of dereliction on the cross, as experiencing abandonment by God, whom he regarded as “Abba, Father”, an experience shared by many mystics, saints, and ordinary folk of all theistic traditions, described at its worst as “the dark night of the soul”. Understood in this way, divine hiddenness poses an existential problem for those who have such experiences.

However, “divine hiddenness” refers to something else in recent philosophical literature, especially since the publication of J.L. Schellenberg’s landmark book, Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason (1993). In this context, it refers to alleged facts about the absence of belief in God’s existence, on the basis of which one might think there is no God. For example, Schellenberg argues that, since there are nonbelievers who are capable of a personal relationship with God and who do not resist it, there is no perfectly loving God, while Stephen Maitzen argues that naturalism better explains the “demographics” of nonbelief than theism and Jason Marsh argues that naturalism better explains “natural nonbelief” than theism. Understood in this way, divine hiddenness constitutes putative evidence for atheism.

Although some of the recent philosophical literature addresses the problem understood in the first way (e.g., DeWeese-Boyd 2016; Garcia 2002; Nagasawa 2015), this entry focuses on divine hiddenness understood in the second way. The first section discusses the relationships between nonbelief and another source of alleged evidence for atheism: evil. The second section states and defends the argument from nonresistant nonbelief. The third section sketches attempts to explain nonresistant nonbelief from a theistic perspective. The fourth section states other responses to the argument from nonresistant nonbelief. The fifth section discusses the argument from the demographics of nonbelief and the sixth section discusses the argument from natural nonbelief.

1. Relationships between nonbelief and evil

Several relationships between nonbelief and evil appear when we view them as providing evidence for atheism.

(A) It is customary to distinguish “logical” (“deductive”) arguments from evil from “evidential” (“inductive”, “abductive”, “probabilistic”) arguments from evil. There are different ways to draw that distinction. On one way (Howard-Snyder 1996c), a logical argument from evil affirms of some known fact about evil that it is incompatible with theism (e.g., Mackie 1955; Schellenberg 2007a), while an evidential argument from evil does not—either because it affirms that the fact in question, although incompatible with theism, is not known but only reasonably believed to be the case (e.g., Rowe 1979), or because it affirms that the fact in question, though known, is more unlikely on theism than on some competing hypothesis (e.g., Draper 1989; Oppy 2013). Likewise for nonbelief. A logical argument from nonbelief affirms of some known fact about nonbelief that it is incompatible with the existence of God (Drange 1998), while an evidential argument from nonbelief does not—either because it affirms that the fact in question, although incompatible with theism, is not known but only reasonably believed (Schellenberg 1993, 2015), or because it affirms that the fact in question, though known, is more unlikely on theism than on some competing hypothesis (Maitzen 2006; Marsh 2013; Anderson and Russell forthcoming).

(B) It is a matter of dispute whether nonbelief provides evidence for atheism independently of evil. Those in favor of independence invite us to imagine a world with no pain, suffering, or moral vice/wrongdoing. No one in such a world would appeal to evil as evidence for atheism, but someone might appeal to nonbelief as evidence for atheism (van Inwagen 2002, 2008; Schellenberg 2010a). Those in favor of dependence tend to define “evil” more broadly. For example, they might say that evils are just bad states of affairs, whether pain, suffering, or moral vice/wrongdoing, on the one hand, or nonbelief, on the other hand (Kvanvig 2002; Evans 2010). Alternatively, they might argue in an Augustinian spirit that, since evil just is a lack of a good that should exist, and since belief in God’s existence is a good that should exist, nonbelief is an evil. One can also affirm that nonbelief is evidence for atheism in the absence of evil while still thinking that the evidential value of nonbelief in this world must account for its interaction with the existence of suffering (Anderson and Russell forthcoming). Indeed, one might argue that the interaction is this: if God has a reason to allow evil, then God has a reason to allow something to act as a defeater for belief in God’s existence (Dumsday 2016).

(C) Even if nonbelief provides evidence for atheism independently of evil, critical responses to arguments from nonbelief and evil share important similarities. For example, just as some critics try to explain why God permits evil, so some critics try to explain why God permits nonbelief. Moreover, just as some critics argue that we are in no position to say that there are no unknown reasons for God to permit evil, so some critics argue that we are in no position to say that there are no unknown reasons for God to permit nonbelief. Furthermore, just as some critics deny the relevant facts about evil, so some critics deny the relevant facts about nonbelief. In addition, just as some people say evil provides evidence against theism only if we conceive of God in certain ways, and so we should conceive of God differently, so some people say that nonbelief provides evidence against theism only if we conceive of God in certain ways, and so we should conceive of God differently. Finally, just as some people grant that evil gives atheism some weight and yet insist that other things give theism much more weight, so some people grant that nonbelief gives atheism some weight and yet insist that other things give theism much more weight.

(D) We can see another connection between arguments from evil and nonbelief by way of one of William Rowe’s evidential arguments from evil. Obviously enough, there is horrific suffering in the world; but, says Rowe, God exists only if there is a reason for God to permit such suffering. However, since there is no reason that we know of, it’s reasonable to infer that there is no reason, period (Rowe 1979). Thus, it’s reasonable to infer that God does not exist. Some critics question the reasonableness of Rowe’s inference from “there is no reason we know of” to “there is no reason, period”, on the grounds that it assumes that we are in a good position to tell whether there is a reason, an assumption they regard as dubious since it would not be the least bit surprising if there were a reason that was accessible to God but not to us. These critics are too quick, however. For we must distinguish two ways in which we might be in a good position to tell whether something exists. The first way is direct: we are in a position to see or mentally apprehend it for ourselves. The second way is indirect: although we are not in a good position to see or mentally apprehend it for ourselves, we are in a good position to see or apprehend something else and, seeing or apprehending that other thing, we are in a good position to infer reasonably that the first thing exists. The critics are too quick because they ignore the second, indirect way in which we might be in a good position to tell whether something exists. This is where nonbelief might come into play. For one might argue that if God’s reasons for permitting a person to undergo horrific suffering were inaccessible to them, then God would make it clear to them that there is such a reason through clear assurances of God’s love and care, clear enough so that they are in a good position to believe that God has a reason to permit their suffering. But many people who suffer do not believe that God has a reason to permit their suffering, not least because they do not believe that God exists. So it is that nonbelief arguably vindicates Rowe’s assumption and inference (Bergmann 2001; Howard-Snyder 1992, 1996b; Rowe 2001; Trakakis 2007b).

(E) An additional connection between evil and nonbelief consists in trying to use various theistically friendly explanations of the facts about evil to address concerns regarding the facts about nonbelief and, conversely, trying to use various theistically friendly explanations of the facts about nonbelief to address concerns regarding the facts about evil. For example, one might argue that just as deep responsibility for each other’s wellbeing explains God’s permission of some sin and suffering, so it explains God’s permission of some nonbelief (Swinburne 1998). Or, alternatively, if there is a good reason for God to permit nonbelief, then God also has good reason not to intervene systematically to prevent or undo the consequences of wrongdoing (for if God did so intervene, God’s existence would be clear enough to prevent nonbelief), and so God has some reason to permit some of the suffering that is a natural consequence of wrongdoing (Dumsday 2015c).

(F) Just as we must distinguish evil providing an argumentative basis for atheism from evil providing a non-argumentative basis for atheism, so we must distinguish nonbelief providing an argumentative basis for atheism from nonbelief providing a non-argumentative basis for atheism. In the case of evil, this might work by “seeing right there in the evil that the world was Godless or that the evil was so repugnant as to be irredeemable” (Gellman 2013: 11). Likewise, in the case of nonbelief, this might work by seeing right there in the nonresistant nonbeliever that the world was Godless or that the nonresistant nonbelief was so repugnant as to be divinely impermissible.

2. The argument from nonresistant nonbelief

More than anyone else, Schellenberg has shaped the contemporary debate over arguments from nonbelief. The main argument from his 1993 book can be stated as follows:

  • (1) There are people who are capable of relating personally to God but who, through no fault of their own, fail to believe.
  • (2) If there is a personal God who is unsurpassably great, then there are no such people.
  • (3) So, there is no such God (from 1 and 2).

For the defense of premise (2), Schellenberg’s reasoning provides the following subargument:

  • (2a) If there is a personal God who is unsurpassably great, then there is a personal God who is unsurpassably loving.
  • (2b) If there is a personal God who is unsurpassably loving, then for any human person H and any time t, if H is at t capable of relating personally to God, H has it within H’s power at t to do so (i.e., will do so, just by choosing), unless H is culpably in a contrary position at t.
  • (2c) For any human person H and any time t, H has it within H’s power at t to relate personally to God only if H at t believes that God exists.
  • (2d) So, if there is a personal God who is unsurpassably great, then for any human person H and any time t, if H is at t capable of relating personally to God, H at t believes that God exists, unless H is culpably in a contrary position at t (from 2a through 2c).

(2d) is tantamount to premise (2) of the main argument.

In his post-1993 writings, Schellenberg clarifies that he means his claims about God, love, and relationship to be necessary truths. Moreover, the main argument of his 2007a replaces talk of “culpability” with talk of “resistance”. (“I now see this focus on culpability and inculpability as a mistake”; 2015a: 54.) And he emphasizes “meaningful conscious relationship”. Finally, his 2015a and 2015b focus on the “openness” of “a perfectly loving God” to “positively meaningful” and “reciprocal conscious relationship”. Thus, the latest version of the argument (slightly condensed):

  • (4) Necessarily, if God exists, then God perfectly loves such finite persons as there may be.
  • (5) Necessarily, if God perfectly loves such finite persons as there may be, then, for any capable finite person S and time t, God is at t open to being in a positively meaningful and reciprocal conscious relationship with S at t.
  • (6) Necessarily, if for any capable finite person S and time t, God is at t open to being in a positively meaningful and reciprocal conscious relationship with S at t, then, for any capable finite person S and time t, it is not the case that S is at t nonresistantly in a state of nonbelief in relation to the proposition that God exists.
  • (7) There is at least one capable finite person S and time t such that S is or was at t nonresistantly in a state of nonbelief in relation to the proposition that God exists.
  • (8) So, it is not the case that God exists. (from 4 through 7)

We turn now to Schellenberg’s defense of his premises.

Schellenberg argues for premise (4) on the basis of what he calls ultimism, the proposition that there is a reality that is ultimate in three ways. A metaphysically ultimate reality, he says,

is something whose existence is the ultimate or most fundamental fact about the nature of things, in terms of which any other fact about what things exist and how they exist would have to be explained in a comprehensive and correct account.

An axiologically ultimate reality “embod[ies] the deepest possible value”, and “would have to be the greatest possible reality”. A soteriologically ultimate reality is a reality in relation to which “the deepest or ultimate human good can be attained” (2015a: 19–21). The idea of a personal reality that is triply ultimate—that is, the idea of God in western philosophy, says Schellenberg—is the idea of the greatest possible person; and, all else being equal, a person perfect in love would be an “improvement” over a person that was not perfect in love (2015a: 89–103; Schellenberg 2005d).

As for premise (5), suppose God perfectly loves Anna. That love would minimally involve benevolence, caring for Anna’s well-being. But it would also involve aiming “at relationship—a conscious and reciprocal relationship that is positively meaningful, allowing for a deep sharing” between them. Moreover, it would involve valuing that relationship for its own sake, and not merely for the sake of something else. Furthermore, it would never cease, and so God would always value, seek, desire, promote, or preserve personal relationship with Anna, although God would not force himself on her. At the very least, says Schellenberg, all this requires that God will always be open to personal relationship with her (2015b: 17–22).

This notion of openness with those who are capable of it—that is, with those who possess the cognitive and affective properties required to participate in a personal relationship, which, in the case of God, would involve such things as a capacity to feel the presence of God, recognizing it as such; a capacity to exhibit attitudes of trust, gratitude, and obedience to God, and so on (2015b: 21n15)—is crucial. Schellenberg writes:

If one is always open in the sense I intend then, even if one does not actively seek or promote personal relationship with another person capable of participating in such relationship…, one makes sure that there is nothing one ever does (in a broad sense including omissions) that would have the result of making such relationship unavailable to the other, preventing her from being able to relate personally to one, even should she then try. So for God to always be open to personal relationship with a relevantly capable created person such as Anna in a manner expressing unsurpassable love is for God to ensure that there is never something God does that prevents her from being able, just by trying, to participate in personal relationship with God…. Anna may not want relationship or even to be reminded of her religious options, and so may through resistance of God, which would have to involve self-deception, herself produce a situation in which she is unable to relate personally to God, just like that, without first undoing the behaviour that led to it. But unless Anna is resistant in this way at a time, she will find it possible to participate in personal relationship with God, and to do so then. Never will she find the door to such relationship closed. This, at the very minimum, is required if God unsurpassably loves Anna in a manner aimed at personal relationship with her. (2015b: 21, substituting “Anna” for “P”)

Expanding on what he means by “resistance of God”, Schellenberg tells us that if we think

first about love and then about openness and then about what it would take for God to allow someone not to be in a position to participate in a personal relationship with the divine, we will see that a sort of free resistance sufficient to make it the case that we ourselves have shut the door to any relationship with God that might be on offer would be required. To trade in one metaphor for another, if God is open to personal relationship then the divine light will remain on unless we close our eyes…. We might imagine a resister wanting to do her own thing without considering God’s view of the matter, or wanting to do something she regards as in fact contrary to the values cultivated in a relationship with God. But it would also involve actions or omissions (at least mental ones) in support of such desire…. Here we might imagine careless investigation of one sort or another in relation to the existence of God, or someone deliberately consorting with people who carelessly fail to believe in God and avoiding those who believe, or just over time mentally drifting, with her own acquiescence, away from any place where she could convincingly be met by evidence of God. (2015: 55–56)

Of course, there are many other ways in which one might “shut the door” or “close one’s eyes” and, as a result, lack belief in God’s existence.

As for (6), by Schellenberg’s lights, Anna could not even begin to be in a positively meaningful, personal relationship with God unless she believed that God exists. Why? Because

a personal relationship is a conscious, reciprocal relationship, and a conscious relationship is a relationship one recognizes oneself to be in. Given these facts, one clearly cannot even get started in a personal relationship without believing that the other party exists. Now belief, as most contemporary philosophers would agree, is involuntary in the sense that one cannot choose to believe something at a time just by trying to. So by God’s not revealing God’s existence, God is doing something that makes it impossible for Anna to participate in personal relationship with God at the relevant time just by trying, and this, according to our definition of openness, is precisely what is involved in God’s not being open to having such a relationship with Anna then. (2015b: 23, substituting “God” and “Anna” for “B” and “A”)

The upshot is that, if God is open to being in a positively meaningful, reciprocal, and conscious relationship with Anna, then, at any time that she is capable of such a relationship, Anna will believe that God exists—unless she has done something that results in her being resistant to such a relationship at that time.

Although Schellenberg emphasizes the point that perfect love seeks relationships for their own sake, and not merely for the sake of something else, there are additional benefits one should bear in mind that may be jeopardized by divine hiddenness. For consider the benefits to Anna if she were in a positively meaningful, explicit, reciprocal conscious relationship with God, even if just one that was developmentally in its infancy. First, there would be moral benefits, e.g., she would be able to draw on the resources of that relationship to overcome flaws in her character, and so she would be more likely to emulate the self-giving love with which she was loved, and thus more likely to flourish as a finite person. Second, there would be experiential benefits. She would be, e.g., more likely to experience peace and joy stemming from her belief that she is properly related to her Maker, and security in believing that, ultimately, all shall be well even if she suffers in the meantime; and she would have the profound pleasure of God’s loving presence. As a consequence of these moral and experiential benefits, Anna’s relationships with others would likely improve (Schellenberg 1993: 19ff).

As for the empirical premise—(7), and the earlier (1)—Schellenberg generalizes from (a) honest seekers of the truth who remain agnostics and atheists, including those whose search leads them to convert to nontheistic religions, (b) members of cultures that lack the idea of a personal God altogether, e.g., the Chinese in the period from the beginning of their history until the Christian Middle Ages, (c) hunter-gatherers prior to recorded history, and (d) those who have lost their theistic faith, and who would like nothing more than to regain it. Furthermore, Schellenberg appeals to increased secularity, especially in Western cultures: what is the probability that all of the hundreds of millions of nonbelievers in the secular West are, at the dawn of their capacity to relate personally with God, resistant? Vanishingly small (2015: 76ff; 2007a: 205, 228ff).

3. Attempts to explain nonresistant nonbelief theistically

It follows from Schellenberg’s premises (4)(6) that, necessarily, if God exists, then, for any capable finite person S and time t, it is not the case that S is at t nonresistantly in a state of nonbelief in relation to the proposition that God exists. In short, God’s existence entails there’s never any nonresistant nonbelief. To assess this implication we must assess the premises from which it follows. In this section, we focus on premise (5) and a particular kind of assessment, something analogous to theodicy in the literature on the problem of evil. To help us keep our focus, suppose we grant premises (4) and (6). Moreover, since we want to assess premise (5) from as sympathetic a position as we can, suppose we grant Schellenberg’s claim that one is open to a positively meaningful, reciprocal, and conscious relationship with another, in a manner consistent with perfect love, only if one never does anything (by commission or omission) that would result in the other being prevented from participating in that relationship, just by trying. Given these suppositions, we might wonder whether it is possible that God perfectly loves such finite persons as there may be and yet, for at least some of them, God does something (by commission or omission) that results in them lacking belief in God’s existence—even though they have the capacity for a positively meaningful and reciprocal conscious relationship with God and they are not in a state of resistance to God. In particular, we might wonder whether there are any reasons for a perfectly loving God to do something (by commission or omission) that would result in nonresistant nonbelief in persons who are capable of relating personally with God in this way.

There are many cases of this type to wonder about. Here are two. First, imagine someone who has always lacked belief and who has always lacked the capacity to relate personally with God but who is, nonetheless, nonresistant to God. Such a person might be a child who is at the dawn of her capacity to relate personally with God. Might there be good enough reason, consistent with perfect love, for God to do something (by commission or omission) that results in her being prevented from belief, even as she transitions to being capable of relating personally with God while remaining nonresistant? Second, imagine a man who has had the capacity to relate personally with God for some time, and who was once a fulfilled nonresistant believer but who, for one reason or another, is now in a state of resistant nonbelief. Many a university student might satisfy this description, among others. Might there be good enough reason, consistent with perfect love, for God to do something (by commission or omission) that results in that man being prevented from belief in God’s existence even as, later in life, he transitions back to being nonresistant?

Affirmative answers to these questions involve reasons for thinking it would be better if they remained nonbelievers, at least for a time, despite their transitions. For example, what if the child never ever exercised any influence over whether she was nonresistant to God? Perhaps, in that case, it would be better—for her, and for God, and for their forthcoming relationship—if she were first to own her good disposition toward God through choices in the face of contrary inclinations, so that, among other things, her loving and obeying God was of her own accord when she came to believe. Or perhaps her non-resistance to God is grounded in improper motives, e.g., fear of punishment, a desire for parental approval or social acceptance, and the like, and so God gives her the opportunity to change her motives so that, upon coming to believe, her love and obedience are more properly motivated (Howard-Snyder 1996a, 2015; cf. Schellenberg 2017a). Or perhaps her moral autonomy, freedom, or moral development would be objectionably thwarted or reduced if God were to bring her to belief at this time (Hick 1966; Murray 2002; Paytas 2017, 2019; Swinburne 1979). Or perhaps, despite her non-resistance, if she came to belief now instead of later, the passion and intensity of her desire for God would be significantly less than it otherwise would be. Or perhaps she is disposed, upon coming to believe now, to think she has arrived at a proper understanding of God, and she would become complacent or relate to God at a superficial level. (Kierkegaard 1844: 28–29, 33–35; cf. Schellenberg 1993: 160ff). Or perhaps certain intellectual temptations would be lost on her if she were to believe now, and so she would not have the opportunity to respond to them virtuously (Butler 1736: part 2, chapter 6; cf. Schellenberg 1993: 168ff). Or perhaps upon coming to believe now, she would be resentful or envious of God’s glory and greatness (Dumsday 2012a). Or what if the university student, despite his forthcoming return to non-resistance, was disposed to relate to God in presumptuous or arrogant ways upon regaining belief, and not with due contrition and humility, both of which are essential to a proper relationship with God? Or what if he was disposed to be significantly less apt to recognize the wretchedness of living life on his own, without God, if he were to regain belief now instead of later? (Pascal 1670, Fragments 234, 378, 427, 446, 449; cf. Schellenberg 1993: 136ff). Or what if God does not bring him to belief because he is ill-disposed to the sort of moral transformation God intends for him, or he’s into having a relationship with God just for the pleasure and titillation of it? (Dumsday 2014b; Moser 2002, 2008b) Or what if God does not bring him to belief because, as a general policy, God permits some people in positions like his to continue in nonbelief in order to increase diverse expressions of religious imagination, creativity, and devotion, or in order to increase opportunities for people to pursue knowledge of important matters together, even knowledge as important as knowledge of God, or in order to promote assisting each other in starting personal relationships with God (Dumsday 2010b; Schellenberg 1993: 181ff; Swinburne 1998); or because, under present circumstances, bringing all non-resistant believers to belief would force the truth of theism on the resistant (Dumsday 2016a)? And there are other explanations offered as well.

Several points have emerged in the literature with respect to assessing these reasons or explanations.

First, it’s doubtful that any single one of them offers a total explanation of nonresistant nonbelief. Different kinds of nonresistant nonbelievers, given the rest of their psychology, might call for different explanations. Moreover, each of these explanations, taken alone, might fail to provide a total explanation of any particular kind or instance of nonresistant nonbelief, and yet each of them might provide a partial explanation and, taken together with others, add up to a total explanation. At least this is a possibility that must not be overlooked. Thus, if we are to reject these explanations, and others that might be proffered, we must claim that they fail, collectively as well as individually, to account for why God might permit nonresistant nonbelief.

Second, in light of the foregoing point, even if there are some nonresistant nonbelievers, it may well be quite difficult to discern whether they possess or fail to possess those motivations, attitudes, and dispositions that allegedly explain their nonbelief in a theistically friendly fashion. If the difficulty is severe enough, then it might be that no one—whether theists, atheists, agnostics, or what-have-you—is well-positioned to say that there are some nonresistant nonbelievers.

Of course—and this is the third point—we might well argue that these explanations provide no good reason, individually or collectively, for God to permit nonresistant nonbelief. That’s because the good states of affairs to which they appeal can be accommodated within a developing, positively meaningful, reciprocal, and conscious relationship with God, or because the benefits of such a relationship with God exceed the goods to which these explanations appeal, or because, more generally, this sort of relationship with God is the greatest good and so God wouldn’t pursue lesser goods at its expense (Bozzo 2019; Howard-Snyder and Moser 2002a; Schellenberg 1993, 1996, 2005a, 2005b, 2007a, 2015a, 2017a; McBrayer and Swenson 2012; Teeninga 2017, 2019, 2020; Trakakis 2007a).

Fourth, one might worry that the whole enterprise of providing a theistically friendly explanation of nonresistant nonbelief is misguided. After all, if God exists, why didn’t God create a world in which there never was or ever will be any nonresistant nonbelief? Why would God create or permit resisters and nonbelievers in the first place? Surely he could have created persons who never resisted and always believed.

4. Other assessments of the argument from nonresistant nonbelief

Even if no theistically friendly explanation of nonresistant nonbelief we know of completely satisfies us, we might yet wonder about Schellenberg’s premise (4): necessarily, if God exists, then God perfectly loves such finite persons as there may be.

On the one hand, we might wonder whether, if God exists, God perfectly loves anyone. In this connection, some critics have pointed out that many “classical theists” affirm a conception of God according to which God is transcendent, ineffable, and/or extracategorical, and so beyond all human comprehension, and so neither personal nor non-personal, and so neither loving nor non-loving (Rea 2015; Ross 2002; Trakakis 2015; Wojtysiak 2021). It is certainly less than clear whether a conscious, reciprocal personal relationship with the God of apophaticism is possible and, even if it is possible, whether it would count as “meaningful” in Schellenberg’s sense (Howard-Snyder 2017a, 2017b; Rea 2016, 2018). Moreover, even if there is a personal God, God might be indifferent to finite created persons, and so not love them—an implication of some versions of Deism.

On the other hand, we might wonder whether, even if God is perfect in love, God would perfectly love such finite persons as there may be. For, in light of an idea suggested as worthy of consideration by Hud Hudson in private correspondence,

to love perfectly is for one’s love to be in the right proportion to the object of one’s love, everything considered—loving to the degree that matches the degree of worthiness to be loved.

Therefore, even if God is perfectly loving, it does not follow that God loves such finite persons as there may be since they may have polluted themselves, rendered themselves utterly unlovable; “and it is, of course, no symptom of a disordered love to fail to love the unlovable”.

One might also wonder about premise (5): necessarily, if God perfectly loves such finite persons as there may be, then, for any capable finite person S and time t, God is at t open to being in a positively meaningful and reciprocal conscious relationship with S at t. Whether this is true might depend on what sort of love is perfect, whether it is more like that of a mother for her child, or a grandparent for her distant descendants, or a benevolent reconstructive surgeon for her patient (Cuneo 2013; McGinnis 2015; Rea 2015; Schellenberg 2013). One might argue that premise (5) is true only if perfect love is like the first, but wonder what follows if it is like the second or third. In this connection, imagine that what it is for God to perfectly love us is for God to provide for our greatest good, and suppose that our greatest good consists in our being virtuous, caring for our environment and other creatures. In that case, it is not at all clear that openness to a personal relationship of the sort Schellenberg imagines is necessary. So long as God has made our flourishing achievable, that is all that God’s perfect love should lead us to expect. In a similar vein, one might argue that “God loves every human but loves some more than others,” and so “God would not seek the same for each person as lovers do not act impartially between those most loved and others whom they love,” and so a “variable divine love” does not require “that God would always be open to a personal relationship with every person” (Jordan 2021; see Schellenberg 2021b for criticism).

Furthermore, one might call into question why God’s love should be our only guide as to whether God would be open to a positively meaningful, reciprocal, conscious relationship. God’s transcendence (Rea 2016, 2018) and/or personality (Rea 2012, 2018; for critique, see Parker 2012, Schellenberg 2017a) might jointly determine, along with God’s perfect love, the extent to which God is thus open.

Suppose we grant Schellenberg’s understanding of openness to relationship as well as his premise (6), and suppose we concede that no theistically friendly explanation of nonresistant nonbelief we know of is wholly satisfactory, either individually or collectively. Even so, we might wonder whether we should infer that a perfectly loving God would not permit nonresistant nonbelief. After all, an open-minded and intellectually humble inquirer will want to satisfy her natural curiosity about whether she is in a position to tell whether there are any reasons for God to permit nonresistant nonbelief that, although inaccessible to her, would be accessible to God. For suppose that she were to discover that, even if there is no good basis for thinking there is a God, and even if she does not know of any wholly satisfactory reason for God to permit nonresistant nonbelief, she should be in doubt about whether she is in a position to tell whether there are any unknown reasons. In that case, we would expect her open-mindedness and intellectual humility to lead her to refrain from accepting that a perfectly loving God would not permit nonresistant nonbelief and, in refraining from accepting this, she would refrain from accepting premise (5).

This assessment of the argument from nonbelief has its parallel in the problem of evil literature where it is (badly) named “skeptical theism”. It has been explicitly used in relation to the argument from nonbelief in Howard-Snyder 2015 and McBrayer and Swenson 2012. For criticism, see Schellenberg 2007a, 2015b. Whether this assessment leads to objectionable skepticism elsewhere is a matter of ongoing debate. For discussion as it relates to the argument from evil, see Dougherty 2014; Dougherty and McBrayer 2014; Howard-Snyder 2009; McBrayer 2010; McBrayer and Howard-Snyder 2013; and Trakakis 2007b.

Even if we accept premises (4) and (5), we might yet wonder about Schellenberg’s premise (6), the claim that God’s openness to a personal relationship with capable nonresistant persons entails that such persons will believe that God exists. Schellenberg argues that a person cannot even “get started” in a personal relationship—specifically, a conscious, reciprocal, positively meaningful relationship with another person—without believing that the other person exists. “After all,” he says, “a personal relationship is a conscious, reciprocal relationship, and a conscious relationship is a relationship one recognizes oneself to be in,” and so “one clearly cannot even get started in a personal relationship without believing that the other party exists” (Schellenberg 2021a, 64).

One might wonder, however, whether one could bring to one’s conscious awareness a relationship that one is in without believing the proposition that the other person exists, for two reasons. First, perhaps one could bring to one’s conscious awareness a relationship that one is in while being in a kind of psychological state toward the proposition that the other person exists other than propositional belief, e.g., credence, confidence, acceptance, propositional trust, propositional hope, or beliefless assuming, as well as non-doxastic faith. Second, perhaps one could bring to one’s conscious awareness a relationship that one is in while believing a proposition that is “thinner” than the “thick” proposition that the other person exists, e.g., the proposition that the other person probably exists, or the proposition that it’s more likely than not that the other person exists, or the proposition that its likely enough that the other person exists to act on it. And there are other options for believing “thinner” propositions as well. (For more on these optional psychological states, see Alston 1996; Audi 2011; Buchak 2018; Cohen 1992; Howard-Snyder 2013, 2016; Howard-Snyder and McKaughan 2022; McKaughan 2013; McKaughan and Howard-Snyder forthcoming; Poston and Dougherty 2007; Schellenberg 2011, 2014; Weidner 2018.) Thus, perhaps one might “get started” in a personal relationship with God—a conscious, reciprocal, positively meaningful personal love relationship with God—without believing that God exists, provided that, e.g., one has non-doxastic faith that God exists and/or one believes that it’s likely enough that God exists to act on it. Indeed, one may well wonder whether propositional belief that God exists would be all that important to God since so many people lack such belief (van Inwagen 2002; Megill and Linford 2017).

Further pressure has been put on premise (6). Some have recently urged that non-propositional knowledge of persons is strongly differentiable from propositional knowledge about those persons, perhaps not even requiring the belief that they exist (Benton 2018; Stump 2018, 2021). If that’s possible, then, perhaps, persons capable of a conscious, reciprocal, positively meaningful personal relationship with God can have such a relationship without believing that God exists. (For critique, see Sweet 2022.)

Some have also recently urged against premise (6) the following argument. It is possible for God to be in a conscious, reciprocal, positively meaningful personal relationship with created persons in a sui generis fashion, specifically, in an “imaging relationship” (Yadav 2020). An imaging relationship is one in which God creates persons in God’s image—i.e., persons “who, like God, are constituted as minds and wills, and like God are capable of employing mind and will to serve the best interests of creation” (76)—and then invites them, through the beauty and goodness of creation, to image God well instead of badly, which, among other things, involves them doing well as cultivators and nurturers of, carers-for, and delighters in creation, and them enjoying “a kind of communion with God, a kind of intimate sharing in the divine mind and will, so that [they] may come to find God uniquely formed within [their] own individual personhood” (77). And, closer inspection reveals that it is possible for created persons to be in a (de re) conscious, reciprocal, positively meaningful personal love relationship of this sort with God, and yet not be (de dicto) conscious that God exists, i.e., and yet be a nonbeliever or even a disbeliever (78–81). And so it is possible for created persons to be in a conscious, reciprocal, positively meaningful personal relationship with God and yet not believe that God exists.

Just for the sake of argument, suppose that psychological states other than the propositional belief that God exists can suffice as whatever cognitive requirement for “getting started” in a personal relationship with God involves. We might yet wonder whether those other states are as good as belief that God exists as a cognitive foundation for a personal relationship with God; and, if they are not, we might well question why a perfectly loving God provides less than the best on this score. Furthermore, even if a perfectly loving God might permit less than the best on this score, perhaps we have just as good a reason to think that there are nonresistant people who are in none of the optional psychological states who are capable of relating personally with God as we do to think that there are nonresistant nonbelievers who are capable of relating personally with God—in which case we can modify the latest version of his argument to absorb the force of the point (Schellenberg 2007b, 2015b, 2021a).

Last but not least, we might wonder about premise (7): are there really any nonresistant nonbelievers with a capacity to relate personally with God? Some suggest that, if there are, there aren’t many; after all, everyone has good Pascalian reason to believe that God exists (Jackson 2016). Others say that everyone at least implicitly believes in God, although not under the name “God” or under a description they might recognize as belonging to God (Wainwright 2002). Further, many religions hold that some kind of basic knowledge of God is universal but can be suppressed, sometimes called the “natural knowledge of God” (Green 2013). Paul’s letter to the Romans claims that “since the creation of the world God’s invisible qualities have been clearly seen”. Calvin famously posits that there is a sensus divinitatis that provides us with at least a basic sense of the divine. According to Jonathan Edwards, there is “sufficient light for the knowledge of God”, hence, nonbelievers must fail to believe “divine things” owing to “a dreadful stupidity of mind, occasioning a sottish insensibility of their truth and importance” (quoted in Wainwright 2002). This insensibility consists in a “proneness to idolatry” and a “disregard of eternal things”—dispositions to ignore familiar and obvious considerations, to be swayed by ridicule and deference to people in authority, to be prejudiced against religion, and so on, which impair the God-given ability to reason properly about God. People bring such impairments on themselves (Azadegan 2013a; Henry 2001, 2008; Lehe 2004; Moroney 2000). Of course, one might argue that non-resistant non-believers do not bring such impairments on themselves; rather, they suffer from a “significant disability,” i.e., “spiritual autism,” that prevents them from experiencing God personally, and so prevents them from belief in God’s existence (McFall 2016). Whether such a metaphor is apt or helpful, though, depends in part on important questions in the philosophy of disability, and one ought to be very careful not to misrepresent or instrumentalize autistic persons.

However, if we deny the existence of nonresistant nonbelievers, we must square our denial with the evidence marshalled on behalf of their existence (Schellenberg 2005c). Furthermore, some forms of resistant non-belief should be deeply concerning for the theist, such as psychological resistance provoked by religious trauma and interpersonal hurts generally (Green 2015; Rea 2018; Panchuk 2018). Whether because of suffering or hiddenness, the mere fact that nonbelief is resistant is not necessarily a boon to the theist.

5. The argument from the demographics of nonbelief

According to Maitzen (2006),

Contemporary demographic data illustrate the lopsided distribution of theistic belief. The populace of Saudi Arabia is at least 95 percent Muslim and therefore at least 95 percent theistic, while the populace of Thailand is 95 percent Buddhist and therefore at most 5 percent theistic…. If those data are even roughly accurate, the distribution of theistic belief is at least highly uneven between those two countries, and they are hardly unique in this respect. (179–180)

Other countries and geographic regions display an uneven distribution of belief and nonbelief, even though it is not as stark as it is in Thailand and Saudi Arabia (Pew 2012). According to Maitzen, even if we grant, just for the sake of argument, the success of some of the theistically friendly explanations of nonbelief in individuals, none of them explain the “geographic patchiness” of nonbelief. That’s because those explanations invoke motivations, attitudes, and dispositions that “do not cluster by country or culture so as to show up twenty times more often in Thailand than in Saudi Arabia” (Maitzen 2006: 184). After all, it’s not as though the Thai are twenty times more likely than the Saudis to be resistant to belief in God’s existence, or in need of prompting to recognize the wretchedness of life without God, or in need of the sort of risk that’s required of a passionate faith in God; it’s not as though the Thai are twenty times more likely than the Saudis, upon coming to believe in God’s existence, to be coerced into love, trust, and obedience, or disposed to act out of improper motives like fear of punishment, or be presumptuous in their relationship with God, and so on (2006: 180–185). Indeed, even if we grant, just for the sake of argument again, that there is great value in a diversity of belief and nonbelief in God’s existence,

why doesn’t this valuable diversity flourish within the cultures of Saudi Arabia and Thailand? Naturalistic explanations, including cultural and political explanations offered by social science, have an easier time of it,

compared to theistic explanations since, on naturalism,

the patchiness of theistic belief has everything to do with the notoriously haphazard play of human culture and politics and nothing to do with God: the messy, uneven data have messy, uneven causes. (2006: 183)

Moreover, it seems implausible that God would be selective in the way God related to different people groups, as though God took considerably more pains to make sure that those in the Middle East, rather than Thailand or China or India, came to belief. One would antecedently expect that God would have the motivation and wherewithal to treat all people equally on this score, which is hard to square with God’s love and justice. So it is that the demographics of nonbelief are better explained naturalistically than theistically, and so those demographics constitute evidence for atheism (cf. Zagzebski 1994).

By way of reply, Marsh (2008) draws on Molinism in order to display how the demographics of nonbelief might be more likely on theism than Maitzen suggests. According to Molinism, God knows what free creatures would freely do in counterfactual situations, and God uses this information in the way God governs the universe. So, suppose that God knew that (i) there is a group of persons P

that are such that, no matter what creative act God had performed, if Ps had existed, Ps would have freely rejected God in their earthly lives

had they believed, and “those genuinely deprived of the opportunity to believe in God in this world” belong to that group (2008: 467). Furthermore, since God knows that

these individuals wouldn’t come to love Him short of something like a beatific vision, God sequesters them in order to secure their eventual conversion,

in an afterlife. God’s decision to sequester them “largely cashes out in terms of the geographic circumstances in which they are placed”, and keeps them “innocent for a later time, when they will be in a position truly to love God” upon coming to belief (2008: 468). Finally, suppose that, given the counterfactual profiles of each individual essence, there is no better distribution of belief and nonbelief than the actual one. In this theistically friendly hypothesis, the demographics of nonbelief are at least as expectable on theism as naturalism. Likewise for a Calvinist explanation:

Determinism is true and souls may be divided into two kinds, the Elect and the Non-Elect. The Elects’ souls are born into societal situations in which they are determined to come to the ante mortem beliefs necessary for salvation; the non-Elects’ are born into societal situations in which they’re not, indeed they’re determined to fail to come to these beliefs. (Mawson 2012: 191–192)

Many theists will find Molinist and Calvinist explanations unappealing since they depend on middle knowledge and double predestination respectively. But another difficulty is that the strategy appears, at least at first glance, more than a little bit offensive. One of the great triumphs of modern ethics is the widespread acknowledgement of the moral reprehensibility of considering some people groups inferior to others. Postulating that non-theistic populations are comprised of people who wouldn’t respond appropriately to God no matter what, in this life, seems to flout this insight; and postulating that non-theistic populations are comprised of people who are elect to eternal damnation might be seen in the same light. (For further discussion, see Maitzen 2008; Mawson 2009, 2012.)

Mawson 2012 argues that, on theism, the demographics of nonbelief are expectable, given either of two auxiliary hypotheses. First, suppose God wants everyone to believe, but God wants much more everyone to believe without God’s having to interfere with the freedom of people. Of course, one of the things that people can use their freedom to do is either to spread theistic belief or to restrict the spread of theistic belief. Given that people’s receptivity to theistic belief is dependent on the culture in which they are brought up and so forth, we’d expect to find that belief and nonbelief are distributed unevenly. Second, what if God wants more than anything everyone to believe, say, because it is necessary for salvation? In that case, we must ask what “deadline” God has set for satisfying that desire. Mawson writes:

There are two plausible suggestions for “deadlines” for God: either that he has set for each individual his or her own deadline and set it as the moment of his or her death, or that he has set us collectively one and the same deadline, the Eschaton/Last Judgment. (2012: 194)

If God’s “deadline” is the Last Judgment, then, once again, it’s not the least bit surprising that, since people’s receptivity to theistic belief is dependent on the culture in which they are brought up and so forth, belief and nonbelief are distributed unevenly. Oddly enough, Mawson does not mention a third deadline, the one that Schellenberg has been on about for nearly three decades: the dawn of an individual’s capacity to relate personally with God. If that were God’s “deadline”, would we still expect the uneven distribution of belief and nonbelief we find across the globe?

Baker-Hytch (2016) argues that the uneven distribution of belief and nonbelief is about as likely on theism as on naturalism since (i) the probability of that distribution on what we know about “mutual epistemic dependence” is high, (ii) the probability of what we know about mutual epistemic dependence on “inclusive theism”—the view that the eternal destiny of human beings is not determined by what they believe at their natural deaths—is about the same as it is on naturalism, and (iii) the probability of inclusive theism on theism is much higher than is non-inclusive theism. See Talbot 2014 for a Christian defense of (iii).

To say that we are mutually epistemically dependent is to say that we are

cognitively constituted in such a way that it is a practical necessity that we rely upon testimony for much of what we know about the world and in such a way, moreover, that we are liable to be significantly influenced by what those around us believe, particularly when it comes to matters that aren’t readily susceptible to empirical investigation, including religious matters. (Baker-Hytch 2016: 376)

Mutual epistemic dependence, so understood, says Baker-Hytch, is a consequence of, among other things, “two types of cognitive bias that play a significant role in determining how plausible we will tend to find a given item of testimony”: context biases, such as conformity, prestige, and similarity biases, which together make it much more likely that we accept the testimony of those we personally trust and respect in our communities, and content biases, stemming from the dominance of intuitive processing over reflective processing and the attractiveness of “minimally counterintuitive” ideas, especially religious ones, which are more likely to spread via testimony (Barrett 2011: 52–72; Kahneman 2013; Boyer 2001: 87–100). Thus, given mutual epistemic dependence, we would expect to see considerable divergence in the content of religious beliefs and clustering of those beliefs along geographic and cultural lines. So, (i) seems supported.

In defense of (ii), Baker-Hytch argues that mutual epistemic dependence provides a balance between competing goods such as (a) exercising interpersonal trust and being invulnerable to deception, (b) sharing responsibility for one another’s acquisition of epistemic goods and practicing epistemic self-reliance, and (c) having opportunities to acquire, practice, and perfect the intellectual virtues and freedom from intellectual obstacles and challenges. Since mutual epistemic dependence provides a balance between goods such as these, he claims it wouldn’t be surprising if God were to bring it about; indeed, mutual epistemic dependence seems roughly as likely on inclusive theism as it is on naturalism.

Another important social consideration for hiddenness arguments in general has to do with “defeated evidence” (cf. Anderson 2017). Suppose that God provides sufficient evidence for one to believe that God exists but because we are a social species, another person says or does something that causes one to think differently about one’s evidence. Suppose, for instance, that one is provided with a misleading rebutting or undercutting defeater for evidence that would otherwise be sufficient to believe that God exists. One’s evidence could be defeated by encountering apparent peers with very different experiences and perspectives on the world, and there is a significant overlap between divine hiddenness and the epistemology of disagreement (cf Matheson 2018). It is also possible, however, for one’s evidence to be defeated by the apparent consensus of those one interacts with. All other things being equal, it is usually not rational to believe differently than a majority and especially a super-majority (cf. List 2014). It is at least a question worth asking whether we should expect God not just to provide evidence of God’s existence but to defeat each defeater we acquire through interacting with one another. If it is possible for God to have a reason to allow us to be exposed to unchecked defeaters, it may be that there are broader social networks in which defeaters aggregate or are easier to acquire and that God may have reason not to forbid them.

6. The argument from natural nonbelief

Marsh (2013) focuses on natural nonbelief in God’s existence,

“natural” in the sense of being built into the physical or biological structure of the world, and being generally outside the scope of human agency and control. (2013: 355)

The cognitive science of religion, combined with ethnographic data for pre-industrial cultures (Barrett 2007; Bloom 2009; Stark 2007), show that

early humans, including many anatomically and behaviorally modern humans, originally lacked a concept of God and were religiously restricted to concepts of limited, and sometimes mean, supernatural agents. As a result, many [such humans] failed to believe in God or anything like God. The nonbelief in question was both naturally occurring and nonresistant. (Marsh 2013: 359)

The “millions and millions” of instances of natural, nonresistant nonbelief in early humans is much more surprising on theism than on naturalism, since it is very surprising that “the human mind would be naturally so insensitive to the truth about religion” “given that a perfect God would desire to enter into a divine-human relationship with early humans”, whereas “[g]iven naturalism’s commitment to indifference about whether early humans would be theists”, it’s much less surprising.

Matters get only worse when one adds that (i) Darwinian evolution—“the claim that natural selection, working on random mutation, is the driving force behind much, if not most, evolutionary change” (351)—helps to explain natural nonbelief in early humans and (ii) Darwinian evolution is much more likely on naturalism than theism. As for (i),

there are three basic ways of thinking about religion and natural selection. Religion might be an evolutionary byproduct stemming from mental architecture and capacities that evolved for nonreligious purposes (Barrett 2004); or religion might be adaptive, and so selected for directly (Norenzayan and Shariff 2007); or religion might start out as a byproduct of evolved capacities and later be co-opted for adaptive purposes (Powell and Clarke 2012). No matter which option one favors, the point is that serious religious diversity and early nonbelief in a theistic or theistic-like God is to be expected. (Marsh 2013: 361)

As for (ii), “Darwinism starts out more likely on naturalism than on theism” because “Darwinism is highly optional on theism”, as evidenced by the fact that “an omnipotent God would have many non-Darwinian ways to create minds, bodies, and souls and would not be limited to Darwinian or even physical constraints”, whereas on naturalism, “the options for developing life are much more constrained, especially in the relevant time frame” (360–61).

So it is, says Marsh, that natural, nonresistant nonbelief in early humans constitutes evidence for naturalism over theism and, when combined with Darwinian evolution, that evidential force increases substantially.

Evaluating the argument from natural nonbelief interacts with the cognitive science of religion and the question of what the demographics of belief, nonbelief, and the capacity for belief actually are.

Some have taken the cognitive science of religion to have provided empirical support for the universality of, if not theism, then at least religious impulses friendly to theism (cf. Barrett 2004; Clark and Barrett 2011). One might think the surprisingness of discovering theistically friendly religious impulses outweighs the contingent relationship of evolution and theism to which Marsh points since our expectations are not what is probabilistically relevant, but rather the comparative likelihoods of the rival hypotheses conditioned on the evidence (Anderson 2021).

Others have taken the cognitive science of religion to have debunked or “explained away” religious belief. For example, it is less clear in the case of religion than in other areas what the “Milvian Bridge” is that connects fitness to truth (Wilkins & Griffiths 2012). An evolutionary byproduct is, by definition, selected for reasons independent of its function, and adaptionist accounts of religion do not typically reference truth as the value in virtue of which religion may be adaptive. To whatever extent that it is plausible that evolutionary explanations such as those from the cognitive science of religion successfully undercut religious belief, this only adds greater force to Marsh’s argument as one should find it surprising indeed that God would choose to use an epistemic method susceptible to debunking.

It is possible to have a more mixed perspective on the evidence from the cognitive science of religion. For instance, one might argue that the cognitive science of religion provides the atheist “intellectual aid and comfort”, even though it does little to decide the God debate in favor of the atheist, and yet provides the theist, at best, with a reason to endorse certain theses in reformed epistemology (Penner 2018).

Few philosophers, however, have been willing to take a firm stance on the capacities, beliefs, and practices of hominids that predate our own species or even pre-Holocene homo sapiens which leaves a fair bit of putative natural nonbelief unaccounted for. However, one might argue that “the earthly careers of early humans form a subplot in a much larger human story that constitutes a life of choiceworthy meaning for them whether they had the conceptual resources to grasp that reality or not” (Vandergriff 2016, 36). Whether or not one finds such a line persuasive may hinge on key considerations from the discussion of Schellenberg’s argument, namely, whether or not one thinks God could create such choiceworthy lives without this subplot, and whether the kind of meaningful relationship one should expect God to be invested in could possibly lack “the conceptual resources to grasp that reality.”

Bibliography

  • Aijaz, I. and M. Weidler, 2007, “Some Critical Reflections on the Hiddenness Argument”, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 61(1): 1–23.
  • Aiken, S., 2016, “Does Divine Hiding Undermine Positive Evidential Atheism?”, Religious Studies, 52(2): 205–212.
  • Alston, W.P.,1996, “Belief, Acceptance, and Religious Faith”, in Faith, Freedom, and Rationality: Philosophy of Religion Today, J. Jordan and D. Howard-Snyder (eds.), Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 3–27.
  • Anderson, C., 2017, “Divine Hiddenness: Defeated Evidence”, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements, 81: 119–132.
  • –––, 2021, “Divine Hiddenness: An Evidential Argument”, Philosophical Perspectives, 35(1):5–22.
  • Anderson, C., and J. S. Russell, forthcoming, “Divine Hiddenness and Other Evidence”, Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion.
  • Andrews, M., 2014, “Divine Hiddenness and Affective Forecasting”, Res Cogitans, 5(1): 102–110.
  • Audi, R., 2011, Rationality and Religious Commitment, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Azadegan, E., 2013a, “Divine Hiddenness and Human Sin: The Noetic Effects of Sin”, Journal of Reformed Theology, 7(1): 69–90.
  • –––, 2013b, “Ibn ‘Arabi On the Problem of Divine Hiddenness”, Journal of the Muhyiddin Ibn ‘Arabi Society, 53(1): 49–67.
  • –––, 2014, “Divine Love and the Argument from Divine Hiddenness”, European Journal for the Philosophy of Religion, 6(2): 101–116.
  • Baker-Hytch, M., 2016, “Mutual Epistemic Dependence and the Demographic Divine Hiddenness Problem”, Religious Studies, 52(3): 375–394.
  • Barrett, J., 2004, Why Would Anyone Believe in God? Lanham, MD: Altamira Press.
  • –––, 2007, “Cognitive Science of Religion: What is It and Why is It?”, Religion Compass 1(6): 768–786.
  • –––, 2011, Cognitive Science, Religion, and Theology: From Human Minds to Divine Minds, West Conshohocken, PA: Templeton Press.
  • Benton, M., 2018, “God and Interpersonal Knowledge”, Res Philosophica 95(3): 421–447.
  • Bergmann, M., 2001, “Skeptical Theism and Rowe’s New Evidential Argument from Evil”, Nous, 35(2): 278–296.
  • Bloom, J., 1991, “Why Isn’t the Evidence Clear?”, in Evidence for Faith: Deciding the God Question, J.W. Montgomery (ed.), Dallas: Probe Books, pp. 305–346.
  • Bloom, P., 2007, “Religious Belief as an Evolutionary Accident”, in The Believing Primate: Scientific, Philosophical, and Theological Reflections on the Origin of Religion, M. Murray and J. Schloss (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 118–127.
  • Boyer, P., 2001, Religion Explained: The Human Instincts that Fashion Gods, Spirits, and Ancestors, London: Heinemann.
  • Bozzo, A., 2019, “The Pre-eminent Good Argument”, Religious Studies 56(4): 596–610.
  • Brown, H., 2013, “Incarnation and the Divine Hiddenness Debate”, Heythrop Journal, 54(2): 252–260.
  • Buchak, L., 2018, “When is Faith Rational?”, in Norton Introduction to Philosophy, 2nd edition, New York: W. W. Norton: 115–129.
  • Butler, J., 1736, Analogy of Religion, Natural and Revealed, to the Constitution and Nature, London: Knapton.
  • Coakley, S., 2015, “Divine Hiddenness or Dark Intimacy? How John of the Cross Dissolves A Contemporary Philosophical Dilemma”, in Green and Stump 2015: 229–245.
  • Coffman, E.J. and J. Cervantez, 2011, “Hiddenness, Evidence, and Idolatry”, in Evidence and Religious Belief, K. Clark and R. VanArragon (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 95–113.
  • Cohen, L.J., 1992, An Essay on Belief and Acceptance, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Cordry, B., 2009, “Divine Hiddenness and Belief De Re”, Religious Studies, 45(1): 1–19.
  • Crisp, T., 2013, “On Coercion, Love, and Horrors”, Religious Studies, 49(2): 165–179.
  • Cullison, A., 2010, “Two Solutions to the Problem of Divine Hiddenness”, American Philosophical Quarterly, 47(2): 119–134.
  • Cuneo, T., 2013, “Another Look at Divine Hiddenness”, Religious Studies, 49(2): 151–164.
  • De Cruz, H., 2015, “Divine Hiddenness and the Cognitive Science of Religion”, in Green and Stump 2015: 53–67.
  • DeWeese-Boyd, I., 2015, “Lyric Theodicy: Gerard Manley Hopkins and the Problem of Existential Hiddenness”, in Green and Stump 2015: 260–276.
  • Diller, J., 2013, “The Conceptual Focus of Ultimism: An Object of Religious Concern for Nones and Somes”, Religious Studies, 49(2): 221–233.
  • Dilley, F., 1977, “Fool-Proof Proofs of God?”, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 8: 18–35.
  • Dougherty, T., 2014, “Skeptical Theism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, (Spring 2014 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.) URL=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/skeptical-theism/
  • Dougherty, T. and J. McBrayer, 2014, Skeptical Theism: New Essays, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Drange, T., 1993, “The Argument from Nonbelief”, Religious Studies, 29(4): 417–432.
  • –––, 1998, Nonbelief and Evil, Amherst, NY: Prometheus Press.
  • Draper, P., 1989, “Pain and Pleasure: An Evidential Problem for Theists”, Noûs, 23(3): 331–350.
  • –––, 2002, “Seeking But Not Believing: Confessions of a Practicing Agnostic”, in Howard-Snyder and Moser 2002a: 197–214.
  • Dumsday, T., 2010a, “Divine Hiddenness, Free Will, and the Victims of Wrongdoing”, Faith and Philosophy, 27(4): 423–438.
  • –––, 2010b, “Divine Hiddenness and the Responsibility Argument”, Philosophia Christi, 12: 357–371.
  • –––, 2012a, “Divine Hiddenness and Creaturely Resentment”, International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion, 72(1): 41–51.
  • –––, 2012b, “Divine Hiddenness as Divine Mercy”, Religious Studies, 48(2): 183–198.
  • –––, 2013, “A Thomistic Response to the Problem of Divine Hiddenness”, American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, 87(3): 365–377.
  • –––, 2014a, “Divine Hiddenness and Divine Humility”, Sophia, 53(1): 51–65.
  • –––, 2014b, “Divine Hiddenness and the Opiate of the People”, International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion, 76(2): 193–207.
  • –––, 2014c, “Divine Hiddenness as Deserved”, Faith and Philosophy, 31(3): 286–302.
  • –––, 2015a, “C.S. Lewis on the Problem of Divine Hiddenness”, Anglican Theological Review, 97: 33–51.
  • –––, 2015b, “Divine Hiddenness and Special Revelation”, Religious Studies, 51(2): 241–259.
  • –––, 2015c, “How Divine Hiddenness Sheds Light on the Problem of Evil”, International Philosophical Quarterly, 55(3): 315–323.
  • –––, 2016a, “Divine Hiddenness and the One Sheep”, International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion, 79(1): 69–86.
  • –––, 2016b, “Anti-theism and the Problem of Divine Hiddenness”, Sophia, 55: 179–195.
  • –––, 2016c, “The Problem of Divine Hiddenness: Is the Devil in the Details?” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, 90(3): 395–413.
  • –––, 2016d, “Why the Problem of Evil Undermines the Problem of Divine Hiddenness”, Religious Studies, 52(4): 525–544.
  • –––, 2018, “Divine Hiddenness and Alienation”, Heythrop Journal, 59(3): 433–447.
  • Evans, C.S., 2006, “Can God Be Hidden and Evident at the Same Time? Some Kierkegaardian Reflections”, Faith and Philosophy, 23: 241–253.
  • –––, 2010, Natural Signs and Knowledge of God: A New Look at Theistic Arguments, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Fales, E., 2015, “Journeying in Perplexity”, in Green and Stump 2015: 89–105.
  • Ferreira, M.J., 2002, “A Kierkegaardian View of Divine Hiddenness”, in Howard-Snyder and Moser 2002a: 164–180.
  • Frigo, A., 2011, “The Evidence of the Hidden God: Pascal’s Critique of Natural Theology”, Rivista di Filosofia, 102(2): 193–216.
  • Garcia, L., 2002, “St John of the Cross and the Necessity of Divine Hiddenness”, in Howard-Snyder and Moser 2002a: 83–97.
  • Gellman, J., 2013, “The Experience of Evil and Support for Atheism”, in McBrayer and Howard-Snyder 2013: 98–112.
  • –––, 2015, “The Hidden God of the Jews: Hegel, Reb Nachman, and the Aqedah”, in Green and Stump 2015: 175–191.
  • Greco, J., 2015, “No-Fault Atheism”, in Green and Stump 2015: 109–125.
  • Green, A., 2013, “Cognitive Science and the Natural Knowledge of God”, The Monist, 96(3): 400–421.
  • –––, 2015, “Hiddenness and the Epistemology of Attachment”, in Green and Stump 2015: 139–153.
  • Green, A. and E. Stump (eds.), 2015, Hidden Divinity and Religious Belief: New Perspectives, New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Hanson, N.R., 1976, “Why I Do not Believe”, Continuum, 5: 89–105.
  • Henry, D., 2001, “Does Reasonable Nonbelief Exist?”, Faith and Philosophy, 18(1): 75–92.
  • –––, 2008, “Reasonable Doubts about Reasonable Nonbelief”, Faith and Philosophy, 25(3): 276–289.
  • Hick, J., 1966, Faith and Knowledge, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • Howard-Snyder, D., 1992, “Seeing Through CORNEA”, International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion, 32(1): 25–49.
  • –––, 1996a, “The Argument from Divine Hiddenness”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 26(4): 433–453.
  • –––, 1996b, “The Argument from Inscrutable Evil”, in Howard-Snyder 1996d: 286–310.
  • –––, 1996c, “Introduction”, in Howard-Snyder 1996d: xi–xx.
  • –––, (ed.), 1996d, The Evidential Argument from Evil, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.
  • –––, 2009, “Epistemic Humility, Arguments from Evil, and Moral Skepticism”, Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion, 2: 17–57.
  • –––, 2013, “Propositional Faith: What it is and What it is Not”, American Philosophical Quarterly, 50(4): 357–382.
  • –––, 2015, “Divine Openness and Creaturely Nonresistant Nonbelief”, in Green and Stump 2015: 126–138.
  • –––, 2016, “Does Faith Entail Belief?”, Faith and Philosophy, 33(2): 142–162.
  • –––, 2017a, “Panmetaphoricism”, Religious Studies, 53(1): 25–49.
  • –––, 2017b, “Who or What is God, According to John Hick?”, Topoi, 36(4): 571–586.
  • Howard-Snyder, D., and D. McKaughan, 2022, “Faith and Resilience”, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 91: 205–241.
  • Howard-Snyder, D., and P. Moser (eds.), 2002a, Divine Hiddenness: New Essays, New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2002b, “Introduction: the Hiddenness of God”, in Howard-Snyder and Moser 2002a: 1–23.
  • Jackson, E., 2016, “Wagering Against Divine Hiddenness”, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 8(4): 85–108.
  • Jordan, J., 2012, “The Topography of Divine Love”, Faith and Philosophy, 29(1): 53–69.
  • –––, 2021, “The Argument from Divine Hiddenness and Christian Love”, Roczniki Filozoficzne, 69(3): 87–103.
  • Kahneman, D., 2013, Thinking, Fast and Slow, New York: Farrar, Strauss, & Giroux.
  • Keller, J., 1995, “The Hiddenness of God and the Problem of Evil”, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 37(1): 13–24.
  • Kierkegaard, S., 1844, Philosophical Fragments/Johannes Climacus, H. Hong and E Hong (trans.), Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985.
  • King, R., 2013, “Divine Self-Testimony and the Knowledge of God”, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 74(3): 279–295.
  • Kline, P., 2012, “Absolute Action: Divine Hiddenness in Kierkegaard’s Fear and Trembling”, Modern Theology, 28(3): 503–525.
  • Koehl, A., 2001, “Reformed Epistemology and Diversity”, Faith and Philosophy, 18(2): 168–191.
  • Kvanvig, J., 2002, “Divine Hiddenness: What is the Problem?”, in Howard-Snyder and Moser 2002a: 149–163.
  • Lebens, S., 2020, “Revelation Through Concealment: Kabbalistic Responses to God’s Hiddenness”, European Journal for the Philosophy of Religion, 12(2): 89–108.
  • Lehe, R.T., 2004, “A Response to the Argument from the Reasonableness of Nonbelief”, Faith and Philosophy, 21(2): 159–174.
  • List, C., 2014, “When to Defer to Supermajority Testimony—And When Not”, Essays in Collective Epistemology, Jennifer Lackey (ed), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 240–249.
  • Lovering, R.P., 2004, “Divine Hiddenness and Inculpable Ignorance”, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 56(2/3): 89–107.
  • Mackie, J.L., 1955, “Evil and Omnipotence”, Mind, 64: 200–212.
  • Maitzen, S., 2006, “Divine Hiddenness and the Demographics of Theism”, Religious Studies, 42(2): 177–191.
  • –––, 2008, “Does Molinism Explain the Demographics of Theism?”, Religious Studies, 44(4): 473–477.
  • Marcar, G.P., 2015, “Aquinas’ Quinque Viae: Fools, Evil, and the Hiddenness of God”, Heythrop Journal, 56(1): 67–75.
  • Marsh, J., 2008, “Do the Demographics of Theistic Belief Disconfirm Theism? A Reply to Maitzen”, Religious Studies, 44(4): 465–471.
  • –––, 2013, “Darwin and the Problem of Natural Nonbelief”, The Monist, 96(3): 349–376.
  • Matheson, J., 2018, “Religious Disagreement and Divine hiddenness”, Philosophia Christi, 20(1): 215–225.
  • Mawson, T.J., 2010, “Praying to Stop Being an Atheist”, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 67(3): 173–186.
  • –––, 2009, “Mill’s Argument against Religious Knowledge”, Religious Studies, 45(4): 417–434.
  • –––, 2012, “The Rationality of Classical Theism and Its Demographics”, in Scientific Approaches to the Philosophy of Religion, Y. Nagasawa (ed.), New York: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 184–204.
  • McBrayer, J. 2010, “Skeptical Theism”, Philosophy Compass, 5(7): 611–623.
  • McBrayer, J. and Philip Swenson, 2012, “Scepticism About the Argument from Divine Hiddenness”, Religious Studies, 48(2): 129–150.
  • McBrayer, J. and D. Howard-Snyder (eds.), 2013, The Blackwell Companion to the Problem of Evil, Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
  • McCreary, M., 2010, “Schellenberg on Divine Hiddenness and Religious Scepticism”, Religious Studies, 46(2): 207–225.
  • McFall, M., 2016, “Divine Hiddenness and Spiritual Autism”, Heythrop Journal, 10.1111/heyj.12324
  • McGinnis, J., 2015, “The Hiddenness of ‘Divine Hiddenness’: Divine Love in Medieval Islamic Lands”, in Green and Stump 2015: 157–174.
  • McKaughan, D., 2013, “Authentic Faith and Acknowledged Risk: Dissolving the Problem of Faith and Reason”, Religious Studies, 49(1): 101–124.
  • McKaughan, D., and D. Howard-Snyder, forthcoming, “Faith and Faithfulness”, Faith and Philosophy.
  • McKim, R., 1990, “The Hiddenness of God”, Religious Studies, 26(1): 141–61.
  • –––, 1995, “Review of J.L. Schellenberg, Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason, (1993)”, Faith and Philosophy, 12(2): 269–277.
  • –––, 2001, Religious Ambiguity and Religious Diversity, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Megill, J., and D. Linford, 2017, “On the Unimportance of Theistic Belief”, Essays in the Philosophy of Humanism 25(2): 187–207.
  • Mesle, R., 1988, “Does God Hide from Us? John Hick and Process Theology on Faith, Freedom and Theodicy”, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 24(1): 93–111.
  • Moroney, S., 2000, The Noetic Effects of Sin, Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.
  • Morris, T.V., 1985, “Agnosticism”, Analysis, 45(4): 219–224.
  • –––, 1988, “The Hidden God”, Philosophical Topics, 16(2): 5–21.
  • –––, 1992, “The Hidden God”, in Making Sense of It All: Pascal and the Meaning of Life, Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, pp. 85–108.
  • Moser, P., 2000, Why Isn’t God More Obvious?, Atlanta: RZIM.
  • –––, 2001a, “Divine Hiding”, Philosophia Christi, 2(4): 439–455.
  • –––, 2001b, “A God Who Hides and Seeks”, Philosophia Christi, 2(4): 467–473.
  • –––, 2002, “Cognitive Idolatry and Divine Hiding”, in Howard-Snyder and Moser 2002a: 120–148.
  • –––, 2004, “Divine Hiddenness Does Not Justify Atheism”, and “Reply to Schellenberg”, in Peterson and VanArragon 2004: 42–54, 56–58.
  • –––, 2008a, “Divine Hiddenness, Death, and Meaning”, in Philosophy of Religion: Classic and Contemporary Issues, P. Copan and C. Meister (eds.), Malden, MA: Blackwell, pp. 215–228.
  • –––, 2008b, The Elusive God: Reorienting Religious Epistemology, New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2013b, “God and Evidence: A Cooperative Approach”, European Journal for the Philosophy of Religion, 5(1): 47–61.
  • –––, 2015, “Divine Hiddenness and Self-Sacrifice”, in Green and Stump 2015: 71–88.
  • –––, 2016, “How Not to Defend Evidential Atheism”, Religious Studies, 53(4): 459–465.
  • –––, 2021, “Experiential Dissonance and Divine Hiddenness”, Roczniki Filozoficzne, 69(3): 29–42.
  • –––, 2022, “Divine Hiddenness, Agape Conviction, and Spiritual Discernment”, in Perceiving Things Divine, F. Aquino and P. Gavrilyuk (ed.), New York: Oxford University Press: 177–192.
  • Mullen, J., 2013, “Looking Through Pascal’s Window”, Faith and Philosophy, 30(1): 26–48.
  • Murray, M.J., 1993, “Coercion and the Hiddenness of God”, American Philosophical Quarterly, 30(1): 27–38.
  • –––, 2002, “Deus Absconditus”, in Howard-Snyder and Moser 2002a: 62–82.
  • Murray, M.J. and D. Taylor, 2012, “Hiddenness”, in The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion, 2nd edition, C. Meister and P. Copan (eds.), London and New York: Routledge, pp. 368–377.
  • Nagasawa, Y., 2015, “Silence, Evil, and Shusaku Endo”, in Green and Stump 2015: 246–259.
  • Nemoianu, V.M., 2015, “Pascal on Divine Hiddenness”, International Philosophical Quarterly, 55(3): 325–343.
  • Norenzayan, A. and A. Shariff, 2007, “God is Watching You: Supernatural Agent Concepts Increase Prosocial Behavior in an Anonymous Economic Game”, Psychological Science, 18: 803–809.
  • Oakes, R., 1981, “Religious Experience, Sense-Perception and God’s Essential Unobservability”, Religious Studies, 17(3): 357–367.
  • –––, 2008, “Life, Death, and the Hiddenness of God”, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 64(3): 155–160.
  • O’Connell, J.H., 2013, “Divine Hiddenness: Would More Miracles Solve the Problem?”, Heythrop Journal, 54(2): 261–267.
  • Oppy, G., 2013, “Rowe’s Evidential Arguments from Evil”, in McBrayer and Howard-Snyder 2013: 49–66.
  • Pascal, B., 1670, Pensees, A. J. Krailsheimer (trans.), New York: Penguin, 1995, revised edition.
  • Parker, R., 2014, “A Critical Evaluation of Reason’s Response to the Problem of Divine Hiddenness”, European Journal of Philosophy of Religion, 6(2): 117–138.
  • Paytas, T., 2017, “God’s Awful Majesty Before Our Eyes: Kant’s Moral Justification for Hiddenness”, Kantian Review, 22(1): 133–157.
  • –––, 2019, “Of Providence and Puppet Shows: Divine Hiddenness as Kantian Theodicy”, Faith and Philosophy, 36(1): 56–80.
  • Penelhum, T., 1983, God and Skepticism: A Study in Skepticism and Fideism, Dordrecht: Reidel.
  • –––, 1992, “Butler and Human Ignorance”, in Joseph Butler’s Moral and Religious Thought, C. Cunliffe (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 117–140.
  • –––, 1993, “Reflections on the Ambiguity of the World”, in God, Truth and Reality: Essays in Honour of John Hick, A. Sharma (ed.), New York: St. Martin’s Press, pp. 165–175.
  • –––, 1995, “Faith and Ambiguity”, in Reason and Religious Faith, Boulder, CO: Westview Press, chapter 6.
  • Perlmutter, J., 2016, “Desiring the Hidden God: Knowledge Without Belief”, European Journal for the Philosophy of Religion, 8(4): 51–64
  • Peterson, M.L., and R.J. VanArragon (eds.), 2004, Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Religion, Malden, MA: Blackwell.
  • Pew Research Center, 2012, The Global Religious Landscape: A Report on the Size and Distribution of the World’s Major Religious Groups as of 2010, pp. 45–50. [Pew 2012 available online]
  • Poston, T. and T. Doughtery, 2007, “Divine Hiddenness and the Nature of Belief”, Religious Studies, 43(2): 183–198.
  • Powell, R. and S. Clarke, 2012, “Religion as an Evolutionary Byproduct: A Critique of the Standard Model”, British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 63: 457–486.
  • Rea, M., 2009, “Narrative, Liturgy, and the Hiddenness of God”, in Metaphysics and God: Essays in Honor of Eleonore Stump, Kevin Timpe (ed.), New York: Routledge, pp. 76–96.
  • –––, 2012, “Divine Hiddenness, Divine Silence”, in Philosophy of Religion: An Anthology, 6th edition, L. Pojman and M. Rea (eds.), Boston: Wadsworth/Cengage, pp. 266–275.
  • –––, 2015, “Hiddenness and Transcendence”, in Green and Stump 2015: 210–225.
  • –––, 2018, The Hiddenness of God, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Ross, J.J., 2002, “The Hiddenness of God: A Puzzle or a Real Problem”, in Howard-Snyder and Moser 2002a: 181–196.
  • Roth, J., 1984, “The Silence of God”, Faith and Philosophy, 1(4): 407–420.
  • Rowe, W., 1979, “The Problem of Evil and Some Varieties of Atheism”, American Philosophical Quarterly, 16(4): 335–341.
  • –––, 2001, “Skeptical Theism: A Response to Bergmann”, Nous, 35(2): 297–303.
  • Schellenberg, J.L., 1993, Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • –––, 1996, “Response to Howard-Snyder”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 26(3): 455–462.
  • –––, 2002, “What the Hiddenness of God Reveals: A Collaborative Discussion”, in Howard-Snyder and Moser 2002a: 33–61.
  • –––, 2004, “Divine Hiddenness Justifies Atheism” and “Reply to Moser”, in Peterson and VanArragon 2004: 30–41, 54–56.
  • –––, 2005a, “The Hiddenness Argument Revisited (I)”, Religious Studies, 41(2): 201–215.
  • –––, 2005b, “The Hiddenness Argument Revisited (II)”, Religious Studies, 41(3): 287–303.
  • –––, 2005c, “On Reasonable Nonbelief and Perfect Love: Replies to Lehe and Henry”, Faith and Philosophy, 22(3): 330–342.
  • –––, 2005d, Prolegomena to a Philosophy of Religion, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • –––, 2007a, The Wisdom to Doubt, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • –––, 2007b, “On Not Unnecessarily Darkening the Glass: A Reply to Poston and Dougherty”, Religious Studies, 43(2): 199–204.
  • –––, 2008a, “Response to Tucker on Hiddenness”, Religious Studies, 44(3): 289–293.
  • –––, 2008b, “Reply to Aijaz and Weidler on Hiddenness”, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 64(3): 135–140.
  • –––, 2010a, “The Hiddenness Problem and the Problem of Evil”, Faith and Philosophy, 27(1): 45–60.
  • –––, 2010b, “Divine Hiddenness”, in A Companion to Philosophy of Religion, 2nd edition, C. Taliaferro, P. Draper, and P.L. Quinn (eds.), Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell: 509–518.
  • –––, 2010c, “How to be an Atheist and a Sceptic Too: Response to McCreary”, Religious Studies, 46(2): 227–232.
  • –––, 2011, The Will to Imagine, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • –––, 2013, “Replies to My Colleagues”, Religious Studies, 49(2): 257–285.
  • –––, 2014, “How to Make Faith a Virtue”, in Religious Faith and Intellectual Virtue, L.F. Callahan and T. O’Connor (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press: 74–94.
  • –––, 2015a, The Hiddenness Argument: Philosophy’s New Challenge to Belief in God, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2015b, “Divine Hiddenness and Human Philosophy”, in Green and Stump 2015: 13–32.
  • –––, 2017a, “The Hiddenness Argument”, The Fourth R, 30: 16–22.
  • –––, 2017b, “Divine Hiddenness: Part 1 (Recent Work on the Hiddenness Argument)”, Philosophy Compass, 12: DOI: 10.1111/phc3.12355.
  • –––, 2017c, “Divine Hiddenness: Part 2 (Recent Enlargements of the Discussion)”, Philosophy Compass, 12: DOI: 10.1111/phc3.12413.
  • –––, 2017d, “Evil, Hiddenness, and Atheism”, in Cambridge Companion to the Problem of Evil, C. Meister and P. Moser (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 108–123.
  • –––, 2021a, “The Hiddenness Argument”, Roczniki Filozoficzne, 69(3): 63–66.
  • –––, 2021b, “Comments for my Colleagues”, Roczniki Filozoficzne, 69(3): 231–250.
  • Schlesinger, G., 1984, “The Availability of Evidence in Support of Religious Belief”, Faith and Philosophy, 1(4): 421–436.
  • Schoen, E., 1998, “Perceiving an Imperceptible God”, Religious Studies, 34(4): 433–455.
  • Sorensen, J., 2013, “The Local Problem of God’s Hiddenness: A Critique of Van Inwagen’s Criterion for Philosophical Success”, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 74(3): 297–314.
  • Stark, R., 2007, Discovering God: the Origins of the Great Religions and the Evolution of Belief, New York: HarperCollins.
  • Stump, E., 2018, “Theology and the Knowledge of Persons”, in New Models of Religious Understanding, Fiona Ellis (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press: 172–90.
  • –––, “Theology and the Knowledge of Persons”, Roczniki Filozoficzne, 69(3): 9–28. Reprint of Stump 2018.
  • Sullivan, M., 2015, “The Semantic Problem of Hiddenness”, in Green and Stump 2015: 35–52.
  • Sweet, K., 2022, “Belief, Resistance, and Grace”, European Journal for the Philosophy of Religion, 14(1): 181–205.
  • Swinburne, R., 1979, The Existence of God, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • –––, 1998, Providence and the Problem of Evil, Oxford: Clarendon Press, chapter 11.
  • Taber, T. and T.D. McNabb, 2018, “Is the Problem of Divine Hiddenness and Problem for the Reformed Epistemologist?”, Heythrop Journal, 59(5): 783–793.
  • Talbot, T., 2014, The Inescapable Love of God, 2nd edition, Eugene, OR: Cascade Books.
  • Teeninga, L., 2017, “Divine Hiddenness, Greater Goods, and Accommodation”, Sophia, 56: 589–603.
  • –––, 2019, “Who Must Benefit from Divine Hiddenness?”, Res Philosophica, 96(3): 329–345.
  • –––, 2020. “Divine Hiddenness and the Problem of No Greater Goods”, International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion, 89(2): 107–123.
  • Tracy, D., 1996, “The Hidden God: The Divine Other of Liberation”, Cross Currents, 46(1): 5–16.
  • Trakakis, N., 2003, “What No Eye has Seen: the Skeptical Theist Response to Rowe’s Evidential Argument from Evil”, Philo, 6(2): 250–66.
  • –––, 2007a, “An Epistemically Distant God? A Critique of John Hick’s Response to the Problem of Hiddenness”, Heythrop Journal, 48(2): 214–226.
  • –––, 2007b, The God Beyond Belief: In Defence of William Rowe’s Evidential Argument from Evil, Dordrecht: Springer, chapter 8.
  • –––, 2015, “The Hidden Divinity and What It Reveals”, in Green and Stump 2015: 192–209.
  • Trisel, B.A., 2012, “God’s Silence as an Epistemological Concern”, Philosophical Forum, 43(4): 383–393.
  • Tucker, C., 2008, “Divine Hiddenness and the Value of Divine-Creature Relationships”, Religious Studies, 44(3): 269–287.
  • Vandergriff, K., 2016, “Natural Nonbelief as a Necessary Means to a Life of Choiceworthy Meaning”, Open Theology, 2(1): 34–52.
  • Van Inwagen, P., 2002, “What is the Problem of the Hiddenness of God?”, in Howard-Snyder and Moser 2002a: 24–32.
  • –––, 2008, The Problem of Evil, New York: Oxford University Press, lecture 8.
  • Wainwright, W., 2002, “Jonathan Edwards and the Hiddenness of God”, in Howard-Snyder and Moser 2002a: 98–119.
  • Watkins, E., 2009, “Kant on the Hiddenness of God”, Kantian Review, 14(1): 81–122.
  • Weidler, M. and I. Aijaz, 2013, “Divine Hiddenness and Discrimination: A Philosophical Dilemma”, Sophia, 52(1): 95–114.
  • Weidner, V., 2018, Examining Schellenberg’s Hiddenness Argument, Cham, Switzerland: Palgrave MacMillan.
  • –––, 2021, Divine Hiddenness, New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Wojtysiak, J., 2021, “How To Be a Christian Ultimist”, Roczniki Filozoficzne 69(3): 215–229.
  • Wolterstorff, N., “The Silence of the God Who Speaks”, in Howard-Snyder and Moser 2002a: 215–228.
  • Yadav, S., 2020, “The Hidden Love of God and the Imaging Defense”, in Love: Human and Divine, O. Crisp, J. Arcadi, and J. Wessling (eds.), London, T&T Clark, pp. 63–80.
  • Zagzebski, L., 1994, “Religious Luck”, Faith and Philosophy, 11(3): 397–413.

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Hud Hudson, J.L. Schellenberg, Edward Wierenga, and Edward Zalta for their comments. This publication was made possible through the support of a grant from the Templeton Religion Trust.

Copyright © 2022 by
Daniel Howard-Snyder <Dan.Howard-Snyder@wwu.edu>
Adam Green <greenab3@gmail.com>

Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world-wide funding initiative.
The Encyclopedia Now Needs Your Support
Please Read How You Can Help Keep the Encyclopedia Free